"Capitalism: The Known Reality" first appeared on the site of the Liberty and Power Group Blog on 4 February 2005, and was republished on the site of the Center for a Stateless Society as well.
"CAPITALISM": THE KNOWN REALITY
By Chris Matthew Sciabarra
Reaching out to the Left has been the source of much good
discussion at the Liberty
and Power Group Blog. So I’d like to pick up on that thread, yet
again.
After reading [a] comment by Jake Smith in response to my “Market
Shall Set You Free” post, I took a stroll over to Kevin Carson’s Mutualist
Blog, which he subtitles “Free Market Anti-Capitalism.” It’s a
provocative subtitle, actually. I’ve been having an ongoing discussion with a
friend of mine for months about the nature of capitalism, so any subtitle that
calls for “Free Market Anti-Capitalism” is intriguing on the face of it. (Kevin
also has a very interesting book out, entitled Studies
in Mutualist Political Economy.) He writes:
If the market and the state have
coexisted historically, they can be separated logically. The question of whether
class differences originally arose from successful competition in the market,
and the state was then called in to reinforce the position of the winners; or
whether the class differences first arose from state interference, is a vital
one. The fact that the state has been intertwined with every “actually
existing” market in
history is beside the point; social anarchists themselves face a similar
challenge – that the state has been intertwined with every society in
history. The response, in both cases, is essentially the same – the seeds of a
non-exploitative order exist within every system of exploitation. Our goal, not
only as anarchists but as free market anarchists, is to supplant the state with
voluntary relations. If the absence of something in historical times, in a
society based on division of labor, is a damning challenge – well then, they’re
damned as well as we are.
The questions of whether state capitalism is an inevitable
outgrowth of the free market, of whether decentralized and libertarian forms of
industrial production can exist under worker control in a market society, etc.,
are at least questions on which we can approach the Left with logic and
evidence. They are, for the most part, rational and open to persuasion. At the
very least, there is room for constructive engagement. And remember, it is not
an all-or-nothing matter. It is possible, if nothing else, to reduce the area of
disagreement on a case-by-case basis.
Well, questions concerning “free-market anarchism” aside, I agree that the
market and the state can be separated logically, and I also agree that the class
question is a vital one. And I’m the first to advocate constructive engagement
with all parties. But as I suggested, there is a problem that must be confronted
when dealing with “capitalism.” Let me explain further.
So
much has been said about Ayn Rand’s defense of “capitalism: the unknown ideal”
that we often forget that the very term “capitalism” was coined by the Left. As
F. A. Hayek puts it in the book, Capitalism
and the Historians:
In many ways it is misleading to speak of “capitalism” as though this had been a new and altogether different system which suddenly came into being toward the end of the eighteenth century; we use this term here because it is the most familiar name, but only with great reluctance, since with its modern connotations it is itself largely a creation of that socialist interpretation of economic history with which we are concerned.
Hayek found the term even more misleading because it is almost always “connected
with the idea of the rise of the propertyless proletariat, which by some devious
process have been deprived of their rightful ownership of the tools for their
work.”
And
yet, Rand proudly took up the mantle of “capitalism,” defining it as the only
moral social system consonant with human nature and “based on the recognition of
individual rights, including property rights, in which all property is privately
owned.” For Rand, this “unknown ideal” had been approximated in history but it
had never been practiced in its full, unadulterated laissez-faire form. It was
largely undercut by state intervention.
But
we have to ask here: Did Rand – and do free-market advocates in general –
redefine “capitalism” in such a way as to make it a neologism? (I address the
issue of whether Rand engages in such neologistic redefinition with terms such
as “selfishness,” “altruism,” and even “government” in my books, Ayn
Rand: The Russian Radical and Total
Freedom: Toward a Dialectical Libertarianism.) If real, actual,
historically specific “capitalism” has always entailed
the intervention of the state, are leftists onto something when they “package
deal” state involvement in markets as endemic to capitalism? Of what use is it
to keep claiming that libertarians are champions of “capitalism” when that
system as it
exists is a warped, distorted version of the ideal so many of us
hold dear? (I’m leaving aside questions concerning the possibilities for the
emergence of a genuinely libertarian social system.)
Now,
it may be true, as Ludwig von Mises has argued, that there is a bit of “envy” at
the base of the “anti-capitalistic mentality.” And it may be true that some
socialists would oppose market relationships regardless of the presence of the
state because they oppose the very notion of individual enterprise and private
appropriation. But the fact remains: Laissez-faire capitalism has never existed
in its purest form. Libertarian free-market advocates know this. But even Marx
knew it. He argued that existing systems were only approximations to that pure
form, “adulterated and amalgamated with survivals of former economic
conditions,” the kind of mercantilist and neomercantilist state involvement
whose “antiquated modes of production” had inhibited the progressive character
of markets. (It’s this aspect of Marx’s work that has been captured in Meghnad
Desai’s book Marx’s
Revenge: The Resurgence of Capitalism and the Death of Statist Socialism.)
This
problem of definition is not simply an epistemic one or even a semantic one. It
has practical implications. When neoconservative advocates of U.S. intervention
in the Middle East talk about “nation-building,” about building “free markets”
and “capitalist” social conditions abroad as part of the march toward
“democracy,” those who live in that region of the world do not understand
“capitalism” as anything remotely like the libertarian ideal. (Indeed, neocons
don’t understand it either!) U.S. capitalism as such is equated with “crony
capitalism” or with what Rand called the “New Fascism”: the intimate involvement
of the U.S. government in the protection of business interests at home and
abroad through politico-economic and military intervention. It’s not simply that
the left has “package-dealt” us this bill of goods; it is what exists and
it is what has existed, in an ever-increasingly intense form, from the very
inception of modern “capitalism.”
Indeed, one of the most insidious forms of state intervention has been in the
area of money, banking, and finance. And if Austrian economists are correct that
the boom-bust cycle itself is rooted in the state-banking nexus, then that nexus
and its destabilizing effects have been around in various incarnations ever
since “capitalism” was given its name. And this is certainly something that even
Marx understood. As I put it in my book, Marx,
Hayek, and Utopia,
Marx shares with his Austrian rivals an understanding of the political character
of the business cycle. Yet the implications of his analysis are vastly
different. While [the Austrians] argue for the abolition of central banking, and
the separation of the political sphere from money and credit, Marx advocates
using the credit system as a mechanism for socialist transformation.
Marx believes that capitalism, based on the dualism between
purchase and sale, makes an exchange economy necessary. The exchange process
makes possible the emergence of pseudotransactions through an inflationary
credit system. Like [the Austrians], Marx views the state as the source of
inflation. The state’s central bank is the “pivot” of the credit system. Its
artificially-induced monetary expansion engenders an illusory accumulation
process in which “fictitious money-capital” distorts the structure of prices.
This leads to overproduction and overspeculation. Real prices – those that
reflect actual supply and demand – appear nowhere, until the crisis begins the
necessary corrective measures.
Marx views the business cycle as an extension of intensifying
class struggle. The state’s ability to thrust an arbitrary amount of unbacked
paper money into circulation creates an inflationary dynamic that favors debtors
at the expense of creditors. The credit system becomes an instrument for the
“ever-growing control of industrialists and merchants over the money savings of
all classes of society.” It provides “swindlers” with the ability to buy up
depreciated commodities. Yet the credit system is a historically progressive
institution, according to Marx. Despite its distortive effects, it accelerates
the expansion of the global market and polarizes classes in capitalist society.
It facilitates socialized control of production and capital investment.
One
would find a very similar, though more detailed, analysis in the works of Mises,
Hayek, and Rothbard, with different implications, as I’ve stated above.
… If
libertarians continue to use the word “capitalism” as some kind of ahistorical
ideal, if they refuse to look at the fuller cultural and historical context
within which actual market relations function, they will forever be dismissed by
the Left as rationalist apologists for a state-capitalist reality. That’s
ironic, considering that so many Leftists have been constructivist rationalist
apologists for a different kind of statist reality. But it does not obscure a
very real problem.
Reaching out to the Left or to any other category of intellectuals requires a
translation exercise of sorts. Real communication depends upon a full
clarification of terms; if we end up using the same term to mean different
things, I fear we’ll be talking over each other’s heads for a long time to come.