ABSTRACTS
BIOGRAPHIES
ENDORSEMENTS
REVIEWS
FB DISCUSSION
SCHEDULE
ROGER E. BISSELL, CHRIS MATTHEW SCIABARRA, EDWARD W. YOUNKINS, EDS.
THE DIALECTICS OF LIBERTY:
EXPLORING THE CONTEXT OF HUMAN FREEDOM
FROM MARCH 29 THROUGH APRIL 4, 2020, FACEBOOK "DIALECTICS OF LIBERTY" STUDY GROUP ENGAGED IN A FULL-LENGTH DISCUSSION OF TROY CAMPLIN'S CHAPTER (18): AESTHETICS, RITUAL, PROPERTY, AND FISH: A DIALECTICAL APPROACH TO THE EVOLUTIONARY FOUNDATIONS OF PROPERTY; BELOW IS A TRANSCRIPT OF THAT DIALOGUE'S HIGHLIGHTS AS PREPARED BY TROY CAMPLIN
This discussion can also be found on Medium.com.
Opening Comments
In this chapter, I propose a
Nietzschean dialectical materialism as a feature of the cosmos itself, where
tensions between complementary contraries---paradoxical relations---result in
the emergence of new things, new levels of complexity in the cosmos. Here, no
synthesis is complete, as the tensions between the complementary contraries must
remain in place for the process to continue and, thus, for new structures to
emerge. I propose that this helps us understand systems ranging from atoms to
living cells to social structures.
This evolution is always taking place
in a historical context, in a physical and, later on in evolution, social
environment. Chemical reactions take place because the outermost electrons in an
atom (unless they are Noble gases) do not have full electron shells. In the
lithium atom, there is one electron in a shell that would be more stable if it
had the full complement of eight, or if it could get rid of that one electron.
However, the number of electrons has to match the number of protons in the
nucleus, so since there are three protons, you have to have three electrons.
Equally, fluorine has seven electrons in the outer shell, and that shell would
be more stable if it had eight. However, nine protons means nine electrons, and
so it must have a less stable outer electron shell. Unless, of course, the
lithium and toe fluorine were to react with each other to create lithium
fluoride, a salt in which the electron from the lithium is donated to the shell
of the fluoride, and the two atoms remain attached to each other---resulting in
a complete balance of protons and electrons as well as electron shells at their
lowest energy. The conditions under which this reaction will occur will of
course differ based on the environment---heat, pressure, etc.---as energy is
needed for the reaction to take place. With chemical reactions, you typically
have to go uphill to do downhill, to the lower energy level.
When applied
to vertebrate evolution, we find similar paradoxical relations emerging.
Vertebrates first emerged in a form similar to an organism around today called
the lancelet. These live in large, dense groups in the sand, so it shouldn't be
surprising if their descendants, the fishes, were to typically live in schools.
Vertebrates thus began as highly social, which had the benefit of making finding
a mate easy as well as being protective against predators. When there's a school
of fish, it's hard to focus in on one.
However, as a breeding strategy,
this is very uncertain and high-energy. A lot of eggs and a lot of sperm are
produced, and who knows if it's your egg or sperm that succeeds. Thus, another
breeding strategy emerged: territorialism. With territorialism, the individual
males and females are ensured to pass on their genes. The territory is protected
in order to protect the fertilized eggs, meaning fewer eggs are needed. Since a
single male is going to fertilize those eggs, just enough sperm is needed to
spread over those few eggs. However, in exchange, the (typically, male) fish
then have to defend that territory against both predators that would eat the
eggs and hatchlings and other males of the species that want to take his
territory. As a consequence, many male territorial fish are brightly
colored---as a form of display, as a signal of health, and to attract females.
But this is just one costly display. Another is the performance of ritual dances
on the edge of the territory to discourage other males, and to allow in females.
The instinct of the fish is to protect the territory against anyone trying to
come in. If they do that against females, though, the point is missed entirely.
Ritual dances by both males and females create a space through which the females
are able to move into the territory in order to lay her eggs and either help
tend to them or leave the male to tend to them. It is due to this tension
between needing to keep others out and needing to let a female in that
territorial fishes have evolved bright colors and display rituals.
It is
from territorial lobe-finned fishes that land vertebrates evolved. This means
that territorialism and ritual have deep evolutionary roots. It also means that
ritual, and everything that evolved out of ritual---including all of the arts,
from music to theater to poetry to sculpture---is intimately tied to the
emergence of property. It also means individualism emerged along with the
emergence of property, as we are now talking about fish interacting with each
other on a more one-on-one basis and developing new, differentiating behaviors.
At the same time, those fish did evolve from schooling fish. We are also
always already social, and that sociality remained throughout the vertebrate
line: frogs congregate around ponds (while calling to both attract females and
defend territory), dinosaurs lived in herds and hunted in packs, birds tend to
live in flocks, and mammals too tend to live in herds and hunt in packs.
Sometimes you will find species that live alone (tigers) or in pairs (bald
eagles), but most live in groups, typically with a single male and multiple
females (lions, wildebeest), but sometimes in more complex social structures
(elephants, chimpanzees). Humans have lived every one of these lifestyles,
though more often than not in complex social structures. In each and every case,
though (aside from schooling fish, of course), there is territory which is
defended against (typically, male) members of the same species.
Property
is here to stay. It's an evolved behavioral trait of land vertebrates and is
rooted in our fish brains. Thus, schemes to eliminate private property are
utopianism at its most extreme, an atavistic attempt to return us to being
schooling fish. This is obviously neither possible nor desirable. And while such
a return (if possible) would, as Marx believed, eliminate religion (by
eliminating ritual), it would also eliminate the arts as well, given they too
emerged out of ritual. Human behavior would be literally reduced to the behavior
of a mob, with each reacting only because their neighbor is reacting. Such a
mob, following whoever is most determined to go in any particular direction, is
ripe for takeover by someone who is most determined to lead---and these are
typically the people most attracted to having power.
While such a
scenario can nevertheless come about anyway---especially in places with property
taxes, meaning you are actually paying rent to the real owner of the property:
the government---the possibility of true individual property ownership creates
the conditions which undermine authoritarianism/totalitarianism. The more
decentralized and individualized property ownership is, the more difficult
top-down control will be. This is equally true whenever there are commons, as
demonstrated in the work of Elinor Ostrom. It's the local caretakers who do a
better job of protecting the land and its resources than do government officials
living elsewhere and trying to create a one-size-fits-all system of control.
Of course, none of this implies any particular property rights regime. There
can be what Hayek calls "several property," meaning you can have a combination
of private and public property, including commons, and individual and collective
ownership. This creates the conditions for a variety of ways of living and
making a living, as well as a variety of ways to care for our lands and
environment.
While Marx purported to predict the end of private
property, the combination of dialectical materialism, Nietzschean dialectics,
and deep evolutionary psychology actually demonstrates the deep evolutionary
roots of private property in territorial fish. With the emergence of territory,
rituals, dances, and visual displays emerged to simultaneously protect those
territories from males and let in females to breed. These ritual displays are
the foundations of what becomes the arts and religion in humans, meaning the
arts, religion, and property are deeply connected. One can thus argue about what
rules regarding property are best, but not about whether private property can
ever be abolished. It simply cannot.
Stephan Kinsella:
Troy, are you quite sure you are using the term "several property" correctly
here? "none of this implies any particular property rights regime. There can be
what Hayek calls "several property," meaning you can have a combination of
private and public property, including commons, and individual and collective
ownership." I always thought it was used by a few libertarian/classical liberal
types as basically a synonym for a decentralized but private property order.
Unless I'm misunderstanding what you mean by public or collective
property/ownership. I think Randy Barnett uses the term a lot in The
Structure of Liberty but to my recollection, not exactly as you reference it
here (I could be wrong, just going from memory).
Roger Bissell:
Folks might want to take a look at this 2015 essay by Andy Denis: "Economic
Calculation: Private Property or Several Control?" It's basically an argument
that economic calculation requires not full private property but merely "several
control," and therefore that the Austrian "calculation" argument against
socialism isn't valid. (Though it doesn't claim that there aren't OTHER valid
arguments against socialism.) I've always been leery of utilitarian or empirical
impossibility arguments against socialism and other bad ism's, and this feeds
that concern. Any comments, you econ experts?
http://www.staff.city.ac.uk/andy.denis/denis%20ROPE%20calculation.pdf?fbclid=IwAR1Ar23nEHD649q_EN_i5jQy_zUi24OnZoBWgQOf6LsvSFVA3uDqu_xawHE
Troy Camplin:
Hayek uses the term as a differentiation from pure private property or from
truly communal (tribal) property. It's severed from communally owned property,
but may be owned and controlled by an individual, corporation, government, etc.
This may in fact imply a separation of commons, depending on if we agree that
commons are communally owned (though one could consider them unowned, and thus
open to something other than communal laws).
By "public" I mean government ownership, where the government decides
accessibility to the public. It's not the same as truly communally owned,
tribal, property.
At the same time, while asserting it's a more precise term, Hayek never
precisely defines it. Yet, it does capture the fact that it involves various
kinds of decentralized ownership by various individuals and entities with
various rules.
Stephan Kinsella:
Troy Camplin, I am not deeply read in Hayek because every book I started by him,
I could not finish. I am not a huge Hayek fan, to put it mildly. I thought Randy
Barnett's adoption of the term "several property" in his odd book The
Structure of Liberty was odd, and idiosyncratic, but I thought he at least
he was using it as some sort of rough synonym for private property, if
decentralized and multi-variegated. I never would have thought he meant it to
include state or government owned resources. But mayhap I'm wrong; I haven't
read through the Barnett book in a while.
OTOH I agree that property
rights can take many forms and even Hoppe acknowledges "collective" rights in
terms of easements, etc, see e.g. the first section of "Of
Private, Common, and Public Property and the Rationale for Total Privatization",
Libertarian Papers 3, 1 (2011) (published as "The
Rationale for Total Privatization," Mises Daily (Mar. 14, 2011)).
Troy Camplin:
Indeed, there are those who discuss property rights as being a bundle of rights,
which may include such things as easements, etc.
So long as there are
different kinds of entities which need to own property in order to achieve their
goals, there are going to be several kinds of property from the perspectives of
ownership and rules. I think that "several," used in this way, would then have
to include such things as commons, especially where local property rules have
emerged spontaneously through the various people's interactions on and regarding
that property.
Commons are not really commonly owned so much as commonly
used, and may be open to anyone and everyone, but more often are used by more or
less the same people. One can think of fishing areas in a bay, for example.
Nobody owns the bay; it's open to everyone to use, and a few use it to fish.
Among the fishers, rules will typically emerge regarding designated areas and
quantities in order to prevent over-fishing. Your designated area doesn't have
permanence, and likely isn't heritable. Were you to not fish it for a year,
someone else likely will fish it, and good luck getting that spot back--though,
depending on the reason why you didn't fish the place, the other fishers may
create a space for you to get back in. In any case, it's all very cooperative
and locally-enforced. Cheat, and you will have a hard time continuing to fish
there, or sell your catch in the market. Or have friends.
In the real
world, where you're going to have individual ownership of stuff (like your
computer and car) and property (like your house and land), corporate ownership
(of the property the business owns and maintains), government ownership (ranging
from military bases to national parks and government buildings like the Capitol
Building, for example), and commons, we have to think about what each of these
various kinds of ownership means (or doesn't mean, if you don't think
intellectual property is a "thing"). In any case, whoever owns whatever
property, the fact of the matter is that property ownership is itself a
psychological property with considerable duration among land vertebrates and
social invertebrates. We can't wish them away; we can only come to understand
them, and understand the various forms in which they can come, and the
consequences of having various property rules.
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
Stephan Kinsella - On Hayek: Not even The Road to Serfdom or
Individualism and Economic Order or his edited collection Capitalism and
the Historians!? Say it ain't so! :)
Stephan Kinsella:
Chris Matthew Sciabarra, I could not finish Road to Serfdom; by the time
I got to it I already "got it." I did like the edited collection Capitalism
and the Historians, but probably because he didn't write it. I could not get
through all of Constitution of Liberty or Law, Legislation, and
Liberty.
Troy Camplin, I'm just wondering about the term "several property" and your
usage of it. To be honest I never found it useful as a concept even when
anarcho-libertarian Randy Barnett tried to use it in some of his theories. I
never found it necessary to use this term or concept even once in all my
thinking and writing. I find it vague and ambiguous. My question was---are you
using it correctly.
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
Stephan Kinsella - Fair enough; he's not the easiest writer to read and the
particular books you point to are not among my favorites.
But I do
think, for example, his Individualism and Economic Order is a seminal
work, touching on some of his most important contributions on the subjects of
the use of knowledge in society, tacit knowledge, competition, and the socialist
calculation debate.
Troy Camplin:
I think one can conclude that "using it correctly" is itself ambiguous given the
ambiguity of the term as used by Hayek and others. To the extent your question
resulted in some clarity and clarification, I think it benefited everyone here,
including myself.
Stephan Kinsella:
Chris Matthew Sciabarra, Road to Serfdom was not hard to read, it was
just preaching to the choir by the time I got to it, so I was just too bored to
finish it. Plus, I was on a romantic beer-soaked vacation to Florida with my
girlfriend at the time and I kept finding it hard to give it sufficient
attention. Constitution of Liberty has some nuggets, as does Law,
Legislation, and Liberty, but overall I am never sure of Hayek's overarching
vision of anything. He reminds me of Nozick---a razzle-dazzling dilettante. As
for the knowledge theories, to me they are flawed, for reasons some Misesians
give. But I'm not your typical libertarian; I realize lots of fellow thinkers
admire and have learned from Hayek.
Ed Younkins:
Thank you, Troy, for your excellent article! I ordered your book,
Diaphysics,
but it has not yet arrived. Within the context of your evolving systems
approach, could you explain how free will could possibly have been an emergent
property of the human mind?
Troy Camplin:
With each level of emergent complexity, you get new degrees of freedom.
At the level of quantum physics, there is little real freedom and little real
differentiation. Everything is probabilistic, everything is truly
interchangeable and lacking in individuality.
With the emergence of
atoms, you start to get a more "solid" cosmos, with different kinds of atoms
that behave differently, and the subsequent emergence of molecules with their
own properties. The quantum physical world is stabilized, and we have the
deterministic cosmos emerging. True, there is chaos, but the chaos of chaos
theory is deterministic chaos.
Self-replicating organic molecules
eventually gave rise to complex systems contained within a protective envelope,
which protected the organic chemical network systems within. However, these
systems quite literally took on a life of their own, meaning those cells began
to exhibit features that one could not attribute to the underlying molecules.
For example, it doesn't make any sense to say that a sugar molecule has goals,
but it makes perfect sense to say that a cell has a goal. By being able to move
away from predators and toward food, the cell as a whole has freedoms the
molecules its made of don't have (at least, not without being part of the cell).
In the same way that atoms have emergent properties that differentiate
their behaviors from their constituent electrons, protons, etc., and in the same
way that molecules have emergent properties that differentiate their behaviors
from their constituent atoms, and in the same way that living cells have
emergent properties that differentiate their behaviors from their constituent
molecules (and even systems of molecules), the mind has emergent properties that
differentiate its behaviors from its constituent neurons, glial cells, etc. At
each of these emergent levels of complexity, you find new degrees of freedom,
and each level of complexity has more degrees of freedom. The same is true of
the mind, and especially the human mind.
Humans are able to create
symbolic goals, which is different from the concrete goals all life is capable
of having. The human mind, being emergent from the active, embodied brain, is in
turn capable of affecting the underlying actions of the brain. We can change the
structure of our own brains through the decisions we make at the level of our
minds. It's not instantaneous, but rather takes time, but it can be done. We
have the free will, from this perspective, to change our beliefs and habits.
That is, the mind, in a top-down (mind to brain) fashion is able to change the
structures of the brain that in turn create the mind (bottom-up; brain to mind).
Freedom is an emergent property of the cosmos, and we are the most complex, and
thus most free, entity in the cosmos of which we are currently aware.
Stephan Kinsella:
Troy Camplin, "In the same way that atoms have emergent properties that
differentiate their behaviors from their constituent electrons, protons, etc.,
and in the same way that molecules have emergent properties that differentiate
their behaviors from their constituent atoms, and in the same way that living
cells have emergent properties that differentiate their behaviors from their
constituent molecules (and even systems of molecules), the mind has emergent
properties that differentiate its behaviors from its constituent neurons, glial
cells, etc. At each of these emergent levels of complexity, you find new degrees
of freedom, and each level of complexity has more degrees of freedom. The same
is true of the mind, and especially the human mind."
It seems to me this
ultimately is an argument for downward causation, which is ultimately what you
have to argue for "genuine" free will. This is in fact what David Kelley
explicitly argues (see his final lecture
here) -- The first few "emergent" things you mention are totally explicable
in terms of upward causation, IMO. It's only free will that really requires
downward causation, as far as I can tell---and the idea of downward causation is
nonsensical, at least to me.
Troy Camplin:
Downward causation from cell to biochemistry is also necessarily to explain why
certain cascade of biochemical reactions occur at certain times. The cell qua
cell has an effect on the underlying biochemistry, on what happens when it
happens.
Further, the emergence of atoms stabilized the laws of quantum
physics and stopped their evolution, as the laws that allow atoms to exist
stabilize within those very atoms. That, too, is downward causation.
Emergence means new things with new properties unexplainable at the lower level
emerge. That's why we have different sciences, to study those different levels
of emergent complexity on those terms. Further, those emergent levels have an
effect on what makes them up in order to maintain themselves/those structures.
To claim the cell has no effect whatsoever on the underlying
biochemistry is what's nonsensical to me---and to every biologist.
Stephan Kinsella:
Troy Camplin, I hear you, but I disagree. I think the entire idea of downward
causation is total nonsense. But then, I have similar thoughts about quantum
physics. This is when I like being a layman---I can just have opinions without
having to back them up. :)
Troy Camplin:
Perhaps this way:
Laws emerge from human beings. But then human actions
are affected by the presence of those laws. Yes, humans are the ones doing
things, like enforcing the law and following the law, but the law must exist to
be enforced and followed.
The same is true of any institution. Humans
create them, but the institutions in turn influence/cause different actions and
interactions than would have occurred absent those institutions.
These
are two social examples of top-down causation. Culture is another. They may
sound familiar, especially in conjunction with the third element, the
individual, who is individuated within a given culture and societal
institutions, etc.
Roger Bissell:
Troy's approach seems similar to ideas in Nathaniel Branden's The Psychology
of Self-Esteem and Arthur Koestler's The Act of Creation. Branden
said that one of the fundamental characteristics of all living beings is
self-regulation, and that free will/volition is just a special case of that
power that applies to monitoring and directing one's cognitive processes. He
called it "cognitive self-regulation," and he said that this capacity (which
Rand called "to think or not to think") is the biological basis of free will.
I've always thought that free will (understood as cognitive self-regulation)
is not really a deeper mystery than self-regulation in general---and that if you
can explain how in the heck self-regulation emerged from inanimate matter, you
should get a Nobel Prize! (Actually, I think that philosophers and scientists
such as Daniel Dennett and Antonio Damasio have come fairly close.)
As
for the freedom part, I agree that it is correlated with complexity. This is
especially clear when you consider the difference between animals that only have
perceptual awareness vs. human beings. The lower animals are only aware of the
here-and-now (plus whatever they remember from the past that is relevant to the
present), and their range of possible alternative actions is limited by that.
Human beings, though, being conceptual beings, can project possible or likely
future outcomes of alternative actions, and they can choose how to act from a
wider range of possibilities.
There's your complexity and degrees of
freedom, both of which seem to be greatest for human beings, and which is
strongly tied to our conceptual faculty. Perception is tied to the present,
memory to the past. Conceptualization adds in not just the actual, past and
present, but the potential. Awareness of what can be or might be frees us up
enormously from being limited to reacting to what is.
Now, that is as far
as I am willing (ha-ha) to go with the concept of "free will." I do NOT think
that we have actual power to have done differently than we did in a given
situation. We only have the actual power to choose from among the greater range
of possibilities granted us by our conceptual/imaginative faculty(s), to choose
free from the limitations of the relatively restricted range of alternatives
open to purely perceptual animals.
But in my view, LIKE the lower
animals, we ALWAYS choose what we most want to do in any given situation - i.e.,
under any given conditions - i.e., in an given CONTEXT. We cannot do otherwise.
How could we? (Discussion of this claim is welcome!) We just have more (degrees
of) freedom in the options, one of which we will most want, and then will choose
and do.
So, our "freedom to have done otherwise" is NOT an absolute
power, as (some of) the Objectivists argue, but a CONDITIONAL, CONTEXTUAL power.
IF conditions had been different than they were, we WOULD have been free to have
done differently than we did. I call this "conditional volition." I also call it
"value determinism," since we MUST do what we most want to do. It is my
"dialectical" way of reconciling determinism and free will. :-)
One last
point: I think that "downward" causation is not literally the case. I agree that
we are hierarchically structured entities, but the top-bottom description is
just a metaphor, and a rather anthropomorphic one at that. (Maybe too much like
a pecking order, as in a corporation or the military, with the executive command
"level" being at the "top" of the organizational structure.)
Many animals
have their brains not so much in the TOP of their bodies, as in the FRONT of
their bodies. But even for those animals with the brain NEAR the top, there is
skin and bones ABOVE the brain, and those are controlled ultimately by brain
functions, so the brain is NEVER literally the top of an organism, and its
controlling actions are never COMPLETELY downward causation.
Maybe
whole-->part would capture the idea better. Maybe center-->periphery. We are
systems within systems, so it might be more clarifying to think of ourselves as
being like Chinese dolls in structure than like organismic ladders. Just some
other ways of looking at how we're organized and how we operate.
Troy Camplin:
I think there are many ways in which human beings affect their own actions,
though for most it's not the way we would like to think, where we are always
steering the boat!
Most of the time, we simply react to things. We don't
really think about them, but rather just react. We then rationalize what we did
after the fact, rather than reasoning through it in the moment. At the same
time, there are times when we think about what we did and try to change the way
we react in the future. That is, we reason through why what we did wasn't the
best choice (even if it seemed like the best choice at the time, based on the
immediate values we held at the time), and make the decision to do other than we
did last time. This is rarely a one-shot change in our behavior. It can and
often does take several attempts to make such a change in the way we react to
things, until we get it "right" according to our concept at the time of what is
right. As Hamlet told his mother, if you do not have a virtue, act as though you
have it, until habit sets in and you end up actually having the virtue.
Self-regulation is another interesting issue, and it's one I have particular
interest in because of the fact that I am autistic and, thus, have weak
executive functioning. The executive functioning in the brain acts as a constant
censor, preventing a ton of information from reaching the surface, and
preventing you from just blurting out the first thing that comes into
consciousness. Those of us with weak executive functioning are constantly
bombarded with ideas, information, notions, etc. from our brain, and we can have
a hard time sifting through it all. It can appear like we're not paying
attention or are easily distracted, but it's because of all the stuff running
through our heads all the time. Further, if we're not careful, we'll say (or
write) the first thing that comes to mind. When I'm writing scholarly works,
that's not a problem. Chase that rabbit and see where it goes, and if it goes
nowhere, revise it out; if it goes somewhere, but it doesn't belong in this
piece, you have something for another piece; but if it goes somewhere and is
relevant to the piece, maybe you have a new idea worth investigating. However,
when it happens on Facebook, I can come across as impatient, arrogant, and maybe
even a jerk, since I'm not in a situation where I can revise and moderate what I
think.
When I'm having a conversation with someone, I will often be
quite for a long period of time before speaking up. Or there may be a long pause
when it's my turn to speak. That occurs because I'm consciously censoring myself
to make sure I'm going to say something socially correct and relevant. Because I
don't have an automatic censor in the form of a strong executive function, I
have to do the work consciously. So I know I am choosing what to say and what
not to say, what I'll do or not do. It's a much more conscious effort on my part
than it is for most people, and I suspect that's why I "believe in" free will,
since I have to exercise it almost constantly! Most people don't have to do this
and simply go through life on autopilot, only exercising that free will when
there is a difficult choice that requires thinking through, or in an effort to
fix themselves after they realize that something they are doing isn't working.
Finally, "top-down" shouldn't be seen as a business hierarchy, with a
boss giving orders to his underlings, but rather in the sense of more complex to
less complex. This is a nested hierarchy, where the mind is emergent from the
embodied brain, and the body is made of cells, and those cells are made of
molecules, which are made of atoms, etc. It's internal stabilization of the less
complex by the more complex, emergent phenomena.
Roger Bissell: Last point first, Troy. Yes, more complex to less complex, nested hierarchy. That's how I understand life and consciousness, too. I basically picked up that perspective about 50 years ago from Arthur Koestler's The Act of Creation, which is still one of the five most important books I've ever read.
Previous point: a book you might really enjoy if you haven't read it yet is
George Ainslie's
Breakdown of Will. I don't think it completely rejects the nested
hierarchy view, but it makes the components of personality a more contentious
and rowdy congeries than we might comfortably consider them to be.
Next
point previous: I must be autistic too, because how you describe yourself sounds
a lot like the way I roll. :-) "Weak executive functioning." Ha! There are times
when I can work for hours at a stretch, with deep concentration and focus, if
it's something I'm really intrigued with. Not exactly distractible. But I also
am easily led off into some intriguing area, away from whatever I'm "supposed"
to be working on. I think my main passion in life is what I think of as the
mental or spiritual equivalent of hunter-gathering. No tribal chieftain
functioning for me! Unless no one else is willing to step up, or unless someone
waves enough "green" in front of me for being willing to do it. ;-) But for me,
life is all about seeking the elusive data, fact, or pattern. I find it in
genealogy, in philosophy, in jazz improvisation, in browsing books and essays in
Amazon and Google searches.
Being a devotee of personality type and
temperament theory(s), I have come to label this the "Apollonian" personality
(as against the Promethean, Dionysian, or Epimethean personalities). I don't
quite assign them the way David Keirsey does in his books, of which I think the
best is still his first one (co-authored with Marilyn Bates)
Please Understand Me, but he's in the ballpark, IMO.
Next point
previous: I don't know if Hamlet (Shakespeare) was the FIRST to grasp this point
(what I learned as "fake it till you make it"), but it's very important. George
Weinberg, years ago, wrote a self-help psychology book called
The Action Approach, which advocates this technique/attitude, and the 12
Step recovery programs (for addicts and codependents alike) also strongly
promote it in their meetings and literature. Rand would have called it
"psycho-epistemological retraining." Same difference. All good points!
Troy Camplin:
Thanks for the book recommendations. I think your recommendation of Koestler may
be the tipping point for me given how often I see his name come up.
Winton Bates:
Troy, I enjoyed reading your chapter. There is just one point of clarification I
would like. You write:
"Philosophy, religion, and the arts are how we ritualize our self-awareness of
sex and death."
I can understand from
your article why you say that about religion and the arts, but it isn't obvious
to me why philosophy is included in that category. Would you please elaborate?
Troy Camplin:
Philosophy and the arts were both once upon a time entirely encompassed by
religion. They each branched off from religion, at different times in different
places (and in some places, still haven't separated off). And they still come
back to religion, to explain it, develop it, find inspiration from it.
In truth, I should have also included science, which had its roots in natural
philosophy, which had its roots in religion.
In all cases, we use these
different ways of knowing to try to understand our place in the world, and we
understand, in a way other animals don't seem to understand, that we will one
day die. That is our place in the world: temporary. We come up with explanations
for why that couldn't possibly by the case (heaven, rebirth, Nirvana, etc.) or
try to create ways to make it so it won't be the case, or is at least delayed
(posthumanism), or try to figure out how to reconcile ourselves to our fates.
This is the role of religion, philosophy, religion, and the sciences.
Now, as for sex, from an evolutionary perspective, individual death only emerged
with the emergence of sex. Before that, there was asexual reproduction, creating
clones. If a clone died, there were more clones out there. With sex, your
offspring are only about half you. That gives the species the advantage of
different combinations, allowing for a better chance of survival (clones can be
wiped out more easily by diseases), but at the expense of individual survival
(in the sense of clones). You reproduce to continue to live on, but you only
half live on. You find someone whose beauty is such that you wish to reproduce
them, and with that person pass on your genes. Indeed, beauty makes you want to
reproduce it, and that is true of mates or things you want to paint or write a
poem about.
Thus, sex and death are intimately interconnected. And they
are interconnected within every religion, philosophy, art, and science.
Joel Schlosberg:
Would not this chapter's attempt to extrapolate limits on human behavior from
those of animals lacking in the capacities of reason be obviated by the same
argument that Ayn Rand used to reject racism, with its "claims that the content
of a man's mind (not his cognitive apparatus, but its content) is inherited;
that a man's convictions, values and character are determined before he is born,
by physical forces beyond his control... It is a barnyard or stock-farm version
of collectivism, appropriate to a mentality that differentiates between various
breeds of animals, but not between animals and men"? (It also calls to mind the
line in Edgar Allan Poe's satirical tale of the future "Mellonta Tauta" about
how prairie dogs being the only nonhuman animal that practices democracy proves
"that democracy is a very admirable form of government --- for dogs.")
Troy Camplin:
Very high on the list of things about which Ayn Rand was completely wrong is the
presence of instincts. Humans didn't magically stop having instincts and being
animals at some point in the evolution of human beings. If anything, to
paraphrase Steven Pinker, humans have many more instincts than other animals.
That results in greater complexity because it results in more degrees of freedom
(and rapid learning). The blank slate isn't an option.
David Blowers:
Reason, reflexivity and spiritual peak experiences are all differences between
humans and other organisms so I wouldn't want to feel too limited by our
evolutionary ancestors. For example, plenty of meditators seem to become less
territorial.
Troy Camplin:
We're on a leash, but it's a long one. Too many who think we're on a leash think
it's a short one, and then most of the rest refuse to acknowledge the existence
of the leash at all.
Joel Schlosberg:
As Henry D. Schlinger points out, "Pinker is simply wrong about the positions of
many of those he accuses as blank slate advocates... if Pinker were to report
their works accurately, he would find positions that recognized innate
tendencies and traits or, in his words, 'human nature.' For example, John
Watson's book,
Behaviorism, has an entire chapter on instinct and his forgivably naive
interpretation of emotion recognized some basic innate ones."
Rand's
assertion in the above quote that "man's ... cognitive apparatus ... is
inherited" acknowledges a form of instinct, and even Ashley Montagu, whose
assertion that "man has no instincts" has quoted as evidence of a blank-slate
view, clarified that it was no denial of innate constraints on human behavior:
"The very title of the other book from which Ardrey quotes me, The Biosocial
Nature of Man, implies that in my view man is a product both of his biology
and of his social experience. But apparently I did not make myself clear enough.
When I wrote that man must learn everything he comes to know and do as a human
being, I meant, and mean, just that. But what that statement has been
misinterpreted to mean is that everything man does he has to learn. This is
clearly not so, and is not what I wrote nor what I meant. The operative words
are as a human being. I mean and repeat that those behaviors that distinguish
Homo Sapiens as a human being, those behaviors that distinguish him from all
other animals, he has to learn from other human beings. This does not for a
moment imply that there do not exist unique biological potentialities in man for
such behaviors. What the statement does imply is that man lacks any genetically
determined patterns that cause him to exhibit such behaviors."
Joel Schlosberg: "Marx did not believe, as do many contemporary sociologists and psychologists, that there is no such thing as the nature of man; that man at birth is like a blank sheet of paper, on which the culture writes its text. Quite in contrast to this sociological relativism, Marx started out with the idea that man qua man is a recognizable and ascertainable entity; that man can be defined as man not only biologically, anatomically and physiologically, but also psychologically." (https://www.marxists.org/archive/fromm/works/1961/man/ch04.htm?fbclid=IwAR1E3LHyGqxCCTm2AzE3B-opnLEM24e5SQqUelIagk4ynob5ZoN7RWJLxwE)
Troy Camplin:
We have, according to E. O. Wilson (actually, George P. Murdock, whom Wilson is
quoting), identified at least sixty-seven cultural universals (instincts) so
far:
age-grading, athletic sports, bodily adornment, calendar, cleanliness training,
community organization, cooking, cooperative labor, cosmology, courtship,
dancing, decorative art, divination, division of labor, dream interpretation,
education, eschatology, ethics, ethno-botany, etiquette, faith healing, family
feasting, fire-making, folklore, food taboos, funeral rites, games, gestures,
gift-giving, government, greetings, hair styles, hospitality, housing, hygiene,
incest taboos, inheritance rules, joking, kin groups, kinship nomenclature,
language, law, luck superstitions, magic, marriage, mealtimes, medicine,
obstetrics, penal sanctions, personal names, population policy, postnatal care,
pregnancy usages, property rights, propitiation of supernatural beings, puberty
customs, religious ritual, residence rules, sexual restrictions, soul concepts,
status differentiation, surgery, tool-making, trade, visiting, weather control,
and weaving. (Wilson, On Human Nature, 160)
Each of these, in various forms, can be found in every culture, throughout
history. The tendency to do these things is the instinct, while the specific
content is of course learned. My guess is there are many more than just these.
In his book Natural Classicism, Frederick Turner adds combat, gifts,
mime, friendship, lying, love, storytelling, murder taboos, and poetic meter to
the list of sixty-seven. And in The Culture of Hope, and in Beauty,
he gives a list of what he calls neurocharms (208-210), many of which could also
be considered cultural universals, since they are found in every human culture.
Many of these, such as narrative, selecting, classification, musical meter,
tempo, rhythm, tone, melody, harmony, and pattern recognition can be found in
other animals, including chimpanzees, gibbons, and birds. Others, such as giving
meaning to certain color combinations, divination, hypothesis, metaphysical
synthesis, collecting, metaphor, syntactical organization, gymnastics, the
martial arts, mapping, the capacity for geometry and ideography, poetic meter,
cuisine, and massage (which would be a development of mammalian and primate
grooming rituals, which humans also engage in, as any couple can tell you), are
uniquely human.
Again, the presence of the instincts doesn't preclude
learning, and actually make learning much quicker and easier. Language is an
instinct. English or German is learned. Property is an instinct. The specific
property rules are discovered, developed, and learned. And as studies of deaf
people in places where sign language wasn't taught, sign languages emerged
spontaneously simply because other human beings were around. These behaviors
that spontaneously emerge any time groups of people get together are instincts,
and without them there could not be any spontaneous orders of any kind.
Joel Schlosberg:
Well, that settles it! All the anarchists in this group, hang up your black
flags and resign yourselves to the inevitability of government, it's right there
on the list between gift-giving and greetings!
Troy Camplin:
Joel Schlosberg, I wish I had better news on that front, but humans are a social
species of mammal, and that has always meant hierarchies and that has always
meant leaders and followers. If anarchy is anything realizable in the real world
(and not utopian thinking), it's going to end up being something akin to
democracy conceived as a spontaneous order form of governance. It will thus
exhibit power law distributions of political power (meaning the most political
power will be most local, and less and less political power the farther away it
gets from the individual, with a kind of massively weak and decentralized world
governance that would probably resemble the current constellation of NGOs we now
have. And that probably pleases nobody, either, but that's also probably what
we'll realistically ever create given the facts of human nature.
Roger Bissell:
Troy Camplin, If our biological organisms were de-hierarchicalized, the way some
people want to de-hierarchicalize families and businesses, we'd collapse into
little puddles of non-functional protoplasm. :-/
Troy Camplin:
That is correct. And do note that every attempt at such creates that exact
result!
I will note that I do believe there are uses for anarchy (and other utopian
concepts).
One is for analytical purposes. It helps one to understand
other spontaneous orders if you analyze them in their ideal form--as anarchies.
If you understand what an anarchic market looks like (or should look like), you
can better analyze the interactions of other orders on the market. One could say
the same thing about understanding what an anarchic artistic spontaneous order
would look like vs. one influenced by government, market forces, religion, etc.
Another use for anarchy is as an ideal to aim for. For this, let us go
back to the ancient Greeks. Aristotle says that virtue aims at to kalon.
This phrase "to kalon" can be translated as either "the good" or "the
beautiful." Virtue aims at it, but it does not hit it. Why? Think of it in terms
of archery. If you have a bow and arrow (think old bows and arrows, not the
mega-powered ones we have today), you would not aim straight at the target in
order to hit the bull's-eye. If you did that, you would fall short. Why? You
haven't accounted for gravity. To his the bull's-eye, you have to aim high. Only
then will you hit the target. (The Greek term for missing the target, by the
way, is "sin".)
In other words, anarchy is a beautiful/good ideal for
which we should aim in order to get a virtuous society. After all, the world is
full of all kinds of "gravity," including various elements of human nature we
will never in fact overcome. But maybe we can stretch our human nature just
enough to create a virtuous society of liberty.
Robert L Campbell:
Joel Schlosberg, Although I agree with Pinker in very broad terms about
"instincts" and share his rejection of environmental determinism, Pinker is
frequently underinformed about other schools of thought that he decided, early
in his career, he could safely dismiss. If all you knew about Piaget, for
instance, was what Pinker said about him, you would know exactly nothing about
Piaget. So I doubt Pinker has made any careful study of B. F. Skinner, either. I
did notice, however, that the behaviorist irredentist Henry D. Schlinger has
read B. F. Skinner with sufficient care that he does not attribute any notion of
instinct to him.
Robert L Campbell: Troy Camplin, All well and good, but for each instinct on one of these lists, somebody (for instance, an evolutionary psychologist) is taking on the burden of explaining how *Homo sapiens* got it through evolution, which in turn means taking on the burden of accounting for its emergence. We can call the tendency (if one has reasonably normal hearing and reasonably normal control of one's vocal tract) to acquire a spoken language at any early age an instinct. But if we then insist that a key part of what is acquired is a set of special structures, precisely described in the notation of a particular school of linguists---so special are these structures, in fact, that they are not like anything else we ever know or could ever come to know---we will end up concluding that this particular instinct could not have arisen through evolution. Looking at you, Noam Chomsky and Steven Pinker.
Troy Camplin:
Robert L Campbell, not necessarily. Vocal communication is hardly rare in the
animal world. Vervet monkeys have calls explicitly for snakes or eagles or big
cats (meaning they're essentially words). Grammatical structures are inherent in
any animal that engages in cause and effect thinking. Combine these, and you get
language.
Robert L Campbell:
Troy Camplin, Whether calls that vervets make in response to snakes being in
their vicinity amount to words requires a fairly deep analysis of how
communicative acts are structured. It may not be as simple as grammatical
structure being inherent in cause and effect thinking. Meanwhile, Chomsky, who
has always denied that human language is basically a means of communication,
continues to wield considerable influence on cognitive science and language
studies.
Troy Camplin
I'm not concerned with Chomsky's theories per se. Human language is an evolved
trait, or it's a gift from God. Those are the choices. Arbitrary sounds that
symbolize certain objects are words, whether used by humans or vervet monkeys.
Words are used to communicate. If Chomsky says language isn't used primarily to
communicate, he's completely wrong--as completely wrong about anything as anyone
can be about anything. It doesn't matter to me if he's a world-famous linguist
or not--if he makes such nonsensical statements, he's to be disregarded. Which
doesn't mean he's wrong that language is evolved or that it's structurally
evolved in the human brain.
Grammar has subject-verb-object structure
(it doesn't matter the order, just that they are all there or implied). That's
the structure a lion must use to hunt--knowing where it needs to be in order to
capture its prey, and how quickly it needs to be there. That's subject (the lion
itself)--verb (running toward where the prey will be)--object (prey). My point
is that this structure, necessarily found in any species that hunts or is
hunted, gets mapped on the communication apparatus (the territorial mating song
still found in gibbons) and the result is the emergence of language. This comes
about from the brain becoming more complex and more of a generalist in its
structure, meaning various domains overlapped to create new behaviors, among
which was language.
Robert L Campbell:
Troy Camplin, Those are indeed the choices. Although Chomsky was eventually
prodded by Pinker into co-authoring an article that tried to reconcile his
account of language learning with evolutionary biology, I doubt his heart was in
it. He is, after all, the author of a book titled Cartesian Linguistics.
If the trouble Chomsky got himself into was merely a function of certain
peculiar notions regarding language structure, he could safely be dismissed. If
the trouble one of Chomsky's major disciples, Jerry Fodor, got himself into was
merely a consequence of some peculiar assumptions about the nature of human
knowledge, then his entire set of arguments against the possibility of human
beings acquiring new concepts could also be safely dismissed. If Chomsky and
Fodor's presuppositions regarding the nature of knowledge are much more widely
shared, that's a different story. For example: How does the use of a particular
call by vervets symbolize anything in the vervets' environment? Even if a human
observer can take the production of a certain call as standing for the presence
of snakes, how does it function as a symbol *for the vervets*?
Troy Camplin:
Those sounds function as a symbol for the vervets precisely because these are
all important predators, and reacting the wrong way will get you killed. When
the vervets make the snake call, they all sit up and look for the snake. When
the vervets make the "big cat" call, they all run into the nearest tree and into
the branches. When the vervets make the "eagle" call, they all run out of the
tree and gather around the tree trunk. There is no question that they understand
what the sound means, and that each sound has a very particular referent.
Joel Schlosberg:
If only Pinker was merely "underinformed"! When he writes of "the Ayn Randian
fringe" that wants to abolish the income tax rather than reduce it, he sees them
as too absurd to need a counterargument. (And that's not when he's including it
in the "many repugnant movements of the twentieth and twenty-first centuries,
including fascism, Nazism, Bolshevism, the Ayn Randian fringe of libertarianism,
and the American alt-Right and neo-Nazi movements today.") And so much of his
commentary on political issues assumes that anything too extremist will lead to
chaos, which strikes me as sour grapes approach to the ideals of '60s-era
radicals whose party he missed (he's noted that he grew up in a milieu in which
"you couldn't get a date unless you were a Marxist or an anarchist").
Troy Camplin:
Joel Schlosberg, true, but this has nothing to do with his linguistics theories.
Joel Schlosberg:
Ironic that those are fairly close to Chomsky's (though they both have a common
enemy in the squishy liberalism of George Lakoff).
Troy Camplin:
Joel Schlosberg, Lakoff is full of wonderful insights, so long as you avoid
where he goes off the rails with his politics.
There are many people
full of both insights and nonsense. It's a matter of being able to judge between
them.
Joel Schlosberg:
It says a lot about the insularity of modern liberalism that Lakoff's claim to
fame (and wow, it's been a long time since his 15 minutes, hasn't it?) was
pointing out the parallels between nominally private and formal political
structures, that "having a common origin in the national mind, the institutions
of each epoch, whatever be their special functions, must have a family likeness"
as Herbert Spencer put it, without seemingly ever coming across genuine radicals
of any flavor that have made that connection. Whether a classical liberal
"industrial radical" like Spencer, a "personal is political" feminist, a left
Freudian like Wilhelm Reich, etc. -- he seems to be completely ensconced in the
Red Team-Blue Team world. And as Jesse Walker pointed out, Lakoff doesn't seem
to realize that there are libertarians and anarchists who want the state to
neither be your daddy nor your mommy (er, gender-neutral nurturant parent).
Joel Schlosberg:
Until I reread it just now I had completely forgot this paragraph of Jesse
Walker on Lakoff, which is even more pertinent to dialectical concerns. Though I
wonder if for many left-liberals, such an approach isn't so much uninteresting
as unimaginable -- they really do seem to think that their opponents are just
greedy and otherwise malicious, lacking any principles of their own. (Ollman is
an exception, in part due to Chris!)
If Lakoff's frame is limited, then so are his rhetorical skills. One reason to
understand an opponent's frame, after all, is not to overthrow it but to hijack
it---to make a case for your policies in the language of the opposition. The
liberal pundit Matthew Yglesias, for example has suggested that opponents of
Bush's Social Security plan should reject the phrase "private accounts" in favor
of "forced savings," a clever bit of rhetorical ju-jitsu that might have
traction with conservatives skeptical of government requirements. (Of course,
"forced savings" describes the status quo as well, except perhaps the "saving"
part.) Lakoff himself notes that conservatives have learned to dress up
unpopular proposals in liberal lingo, but he doesn't seem interested in teaching
transvestism to the left. (Walker)
Robert L Campbell:
Troy Camplin, I find your exchanges with Joel Schlosberg interesting, because
George Lakoff is by profession a linguist. He was a disciple of Chomsky who made
a noisy exit from the Chomskyan camp during the "generative semantics" schism of
the early 1970s. In the end, I don't see that Lakoff repaired any of Chomsky's
deficiencies, linguistically speaking. Meanwhile, no one in the United States
becomes a public intellectual via linguistics. Lakoff had to venture into
political psychology... Hayek refuted Lakoff in advance when he noted that a
"great society" is not a family writ large.
I'm still not getting why or how vervets are using symbols. When one vervet
gives the "eagle" call the other vervets do what will significantly reduce their
risk of being grabbed up, carried off, and eaten by an eagle. The "eagle" call
elicits the appropriate action in that environment. Do any of the vervets need
to know that that the "eagle" call (I'd insert a notation for what it sounds
like if there was one and I knew it; otherwise a recorded excerpt would be
better) *stands for* an eagle nearby in order to do what will protect them from
an eagle? Does the effectiveness of the call or the response to it depend on
whether the predator that has arrived in their midst is an eagle, or another
bird of prey big enough to carry one of them off? The calls are part of an
action system that helps the vervets survive. Must any such system employ
symbols? If symbols are not automatically required, how do we establish that
this particular mode of communication employs symbols?
Joel Schlosberg: But Herbert Spencer refuted Hayek in advance of Hayek's refutation of Lakoff when he contended that society and the "must have a family likeness" to, um, the family due to their "having a common origin" in the psychology of the people who make up both (as opposed to prescriptively modeling society as one big happy family.) https://books.google.com/books?id=A7XsAAAAMAAJ&pg=PA45&fbclid=IwAR0QjYgbAIQwFB660dMerA9w__DLZctf9y7e4dmSq68H9XKK9h4aYO2Vk8Q#v=onepage&q&f=false
Troy Camplin:
It's a sound symbol representing something real in the world. More tellingly is
their reaction to the call for "snake." When that call is made, they all stand
up and start looking for a snake. When they find it, they tend to gather around
its tail and annoy it until it leaves their territory. This requires a degree of
coordinated effort on their part.
If the vervets didn't know the call
meant "snake" or "eagle" or "big cat," they would not know to make the call when
any of those things were around. An individual has to know what it sees and
choose the right call to make (which also draws attention to itself, so it's
risking its own life making the call). It also has to make a call that the rest
understand to have that particular meaning, and they have to react accordingly.
Yes, each of the sounds has a survival element. That's one of the
reasons communication exists (other species use sounds for territorial
protection or attracting a mate--or both; but it's still a way to communicate
information). Words each provide information distinguishable from the meanings
of other words. They are thus no different form the distinct vervet calls that
all have distinct meanings and communicate to the other vervets what they should
do.
Susan Love Brown:
Troy Camplin, Cultural universals are not instincts.
Troy Camplin:
Yes, they most certainly are. We have an instinct for language the same way a
lion has an instinct for hunting. The fact that learning in each case improves
what the instinct allows the organism to learn more quickly doesn't mean it's
not an instinct.
An instinct is a behavior that gets programmed into the
brain because what is learned is thus more quickly learned as a result. These
instincts are weaker or stronger in some people, and this create variability in
length of learning time. The weaker an instinct is, the longer it takes to learn
something. This is why learning to speak doesn't take as long as learning to
read and write, the latter two of which are artificial technologies (and require
taking over parts of our brain's abilities to recognize faces and shapes/edges).
There are simpler aspects of mathematics that are instinctual, but the
overwhelming majority of math is not and, thus, requires considerable effort to
learn and understand.
There are other things, though, that people learn
and latch onto almost immediately. A good example is the rhythms of poetry.
Children are excellent at creating little sing-song poems with regular rhythms
and of 3-4 second line-lengths. We actually have to make an effort to unlearn
how to write poetry that way, and all too often we do such a good job that we
get out of the habit of what is actually more natural to us. Even with
instincts, you have to keep in practice to improve the learning aspect of the
instincts in question
Instincts allow us to learn a great deal a great
deal more quickly. That's why humans have many more instincts than do other
animals. They allow us to learn more, and thus to live in more complex
societies. Things that are much more difficult to learn, because outside the
realm of our instincts, become areas of extreme specialization for tiny numbers
of elites. Our educational system is greatly hampered by the failure to
understand these things.
David Blowers:
Thanks for a thought-provoking chapter. I'll spread some of the thoughts it
provoked over a few different comments for clarity. I think you shed some light
on the disdain and indifference people feel for government-owned public property
and it's interesting to consider the idea that people are invested in collective
property if they personally know the co-owners. If collective property within
these Dunbar number limits works within this scheme, then why is private
property is always necessitated? For example, you could have (perhaps federated)
anarcho-communes of 150 people each, using collectively owned but not private
property.
Troy Camplin:
David Blowers, it works, but it's extremely limited. It works in sparsely
populated areas. Low density means low complexity.
Complex societies
require domination by weak bonds, and too-strong bonds undermine those weak
bonds. Tribalism of all kinds undermine complex societies, and our goal must
then be to understand how to get beyond those Dunbar numbers, or at least
proliferate them in our lives (in the same way that large corporations still
have departments of around 150).
That being said, if people want to
experiment with anarcho-communes of 150 each, they should. But what we'll
discover is that they'll still want to trade with others, and that this will
necessarily result in capitalism. It will be different, to be sure, but it will
still be fundamentally capitalistic.
There's really no reason people
couldn't voluntarily do that now, so you have to ask why nobody's doing it. The
answer is simple: The free rider problem. Individual private ownership solves
that problem.
Roger Bissell:
Troy Camplin, The example I'm most familiar with is "The Farm," in south
Tennessee. It was founded in 1971 by Stephen and Ina Gaskin. Gaskin was an
ex-marine and hippie who gathered about 300 like-minded Baby Boomers to found
the commune. Its population eventually peaked at about 1600 (largely due to all
the babies midwifed by Ina et al).
In the Wikipedia article linked below,
see the paragraph about The Changeover in 1983, when the membership voted to
change "its residential community agreement and began requiring members to
support themselves with their own income rather than to donate all income to The
Foundation central corporation." Most left in disillusionment, and the current
population is now about 200, just a tad above the number you mention in your
above post.
I remember the scandal of how marijuana was being used as a
"sacrament" here in the Bible Belt. Gaskin and his wife were interviewed on a
local television show on which I played in the band, so I got to see these most
unorthodox (for Middle Tennessee, anyway) up close. They looked and sounded
perfectly normal to me, but I wasn't enticed to leave my budding musical career
in Nashville to be part of the self-sustaining communal life. ;-)
This is
one of a number of interesting articles on The Farm that you can access with a
Google search:
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_Farm_(Tennessee)
Joel Schlosberg:
When you say that any attempt to "trade with others... will necessarily result
in capitalism" is that because any overall market economy with robust trade
would be capitalist by definition, even if it's trade between internally
socialized organizations (as David Friedman notes that capitalist firms are!) or
that it would influence all organizations within it to become internally
capitalist? The latter being, ironically, an argument used by communists against
more market-friendly variety of socialism to contend that restrictions on trade,
rather than being futile, must be pursued even more fully to bring about
socialism!
Troy Camplin:
I suppose it depends on what one means by "capitalism." Too often people mean by
that "the aspects of the current system I hate." If by "capitalism" we mean "the
private ownership and provision of capital," then I'm unsure exactly how much
trade could or would take place or how beneficial free trade would even be
without capitalism. It would all be rather cursory, it seems to me.
Now,
capital is heterogeneous. Money can be capital, but there are also capital
goods. It's when certain capital goods get produced when there's no market
demand for the final goods that you have bubbles that burst. This can't be
prevented by not having capital in private hands, but is instead rather likely
to get exacerbated because of information bottlenecks. Indeed, bubbles are an
information problem insofar as false information is being promulgated through
the system. Information flows are maximized through decentralization and the
emergence of scale free network processes, not through centralization or
politicization. Decentralization is not the same thing as diffuse. With
decentralization, individuals use their local and tacit and personal knowledge
to make decisions, while "democratic" decision-making is diffuse. The average
person wanted a phone they could take with them, but entrepreneurs gave them
smart phones, which they clearly want much more than a mobile phone alone (I'm
writing this on one).
The dissolution of capital would result in the
creation of far fewer new things. The diffusion of capital would have the same
effect. So, too, would the centralization of capital into the hands of
government (which would also face issues of cronyism and other forms of
corruption). From this perspective, only capitalism as the private ownership and
distribution of capital will give you any kind of free trade worth caring
anything about, as it's the best, most effective, most efficient way to create
the new technologies that result in ever-greater wealth for everyone.
Roger Bissell:
Troy Camplin,
There really is a "sweet spot" for capital, isn't there.
Troy Camplin:
Yes, there is. And the clearer our information channels, the more likely we are
to hit that sweet spot.
Joel Schlosberg:
I'll also note that many intentional communities allow more individual property
and initiative than the stereotypical everyone-owns-everything commune (or the
ones like The Farm which explicitly restricted individual property), from Josiah
Warren's Utopia and Modern Times (he identified a lack of individualism as the
reason for the failure of the early utopian socialist community of New Harmony,
then made more successful ones of his own), the single tax colonies, and the
Israeli moshavim.
David Blowers:
This one's a bit tangential but your first paragraph made me come back to a
recurring thing I think about---if there's no end-point to history, such as
Marx's communism, it's a reminder that whatever libertarian societies we achieve
will likely not last (because nothing ever does). Do we struggle forward anyway,
to enjoy the fruits while they last, and because these values are worth the
struggle regardless of the consequences? Or do we give up and muddle through and
become hermits dwelling in mountain caves? I'd really like to become a mountain
hermit so I am trying to persuade myself that it's the latter :)
Troy Camplin:
David Blowers, I think Camus gives the answer in The Plague. You fight
the battle because it's the right thing to do, not knowing if you even made a
difference, knowing all successes are necessarily temporary. We cannot escape
time nor change. Nothing lasts, though there can be substantial durability.
Stephan Kinsella:
Troy Camplin, What reason do we have to think "there can be substantial
durability." ...?
Troy Camplin:
Atoms have substantial durability, but they won't last. Each organism has
substantial durability, but they don't last either (and their substantial
durability is of much more limited duration than an atom, to say the least).
Ecosystems have substantial durability, but they don't last--even if they do
last longer than do individuals or even individual species within them.
Humans live in a variety of epistemic ecosystems--the spontaneous orders of the
catallaxy, culture, philanthropy, religion, philosophy, the sciences,
technological innovation, democracy, etc.--which together create an epistemic
biosphere, or civic society. They all have duration, but none last forever. They
also change considerably over time--you can have grasslands, but the species in
the grasslands may change, and they will certainly differ based on where they're
located (obviously there are different species in the South American pampas,
African savanna, and North American Great Plains, for example). The African
savannas have elephants, but the North American Great Plains no longer have
elephants (mastodons)--and yet, the Great Plains retain many of the same
features, that is, is identifiable as being the Great Plains, though certain
species no longer exist.
The durability of the Great Plains is not
necessarily dependent on any given species' presence, other than the dominance
of grasses, any more than the epistemic ecosystem of the catallaxy requires any
particular set of institutions other than...
And that's what we, as
social scientists, need to discover. What institutions are necessary for the
continuation and maximum health of the particular epistemic ecosystem we call
the catallaxy (or, the free market, which has a combination of epistemic
ecosystems: catallaxy, finance, and technological innovation). What will result
in a considerable amount of duration?
Joel Schlosberg:
I get the impression that many libertarians don't believe that "there's no
end-point to history, such as Marx's communism" but agree with Francis
Fukuyama's thesis that the end point is capitalism! Less statist than Fukuyama's
neocon version (or for that matter Steven Pinker's) with its concessions to
law-and-order and social safety nets, but a static ideal all the same, rather
than Carl Sagan's view that a free society based on open-minded liberal values
would mark "the beginning, much more than the end, of history."
http://www.celebratingsagan.com/.../carl-sagan-beginning.../
Stephan Kinsella:
Troy Camplin, "Atoms have substantial durability, but they won't last. Each
organism has substantial durability, but they don't last either". Not sure how
you know that atoms don't last but ... so what? What is the point of observing
that something that exists doesn't "last", i.e., doesn't exist forever, i.e.,
that things change? Isn't this obvious, by the very nature of time, and
causality itself--that things change... i.e., that nothing stays the same? If
anything stayed the same, wouldn't this imply there is no change, i.e., no time?
Troy Camplin:
You're the one who brought it up.
Stephan Kinsella:
Troy Camplin, Ahh, gotcha. I was just not clear about what you meant by
"substantial durability".
Troy Camplin:
Stephan Kinsella, "What reason do we have to think " there can be substantial
durability." ...?" I just explained it to you. Durability is a feature of the
cosmos at different levels of complexity when you have the right rules in place.
Substantial durability is in contrast with transient, of considerably less
durability. And yes, one does have to designate "substantial durability" because
there are in fact people who believe in permanence, eternal verities, and so on.
Further, there are those who think in such absolutes that if there is any degree
to which something could possibly cease to exist, then it's not "true" or a
"universal." Durability does, then, matter a great deal because it is between
the idea of eternal ideas/forms/verities/etc and pure transience lacking all
possibility of substance.
In the case of a free society, which is what
this was all directed at, the point is that we cannot possibly expect to achieve
the utopian dream of a permanently free society precisely because nothing--not
even atoms--have permanence. What we can hope for is creating systems which have
varying degrees of durability. That requires continuous diligence on the part of
those who love liberty. If we want to have a durable society of longer duration,
we too will have to have durable diligence in arguing for it and maintaining it
and understanding it. We can never permanently win (which was the question David
asked, of whether or not we can ever permanently win), and I was explaining why
we can never permanently win. Nothing is permanent. There are just varying
degrees of durability.
That being the case, and understanding that that
is the case, we then need to ask what institutions could be put in place to
increase durability.
Stephan Kinsella:
Troy Camplin, I'm actually not sure what durability means in this case. You seem
to mean it's something that lasts for some time but not forever. You contrast it
with "transient" but even that fits the description of durability: it lasts for
some time, but not forever. Transience only means the degree of durability,
which seems to be a mere matter of degree not of kind. I am not sure why our
goal is to find institutions that increase durability, rather than some other
value, like liberty or justice. If someone is defending himself or his family or
kith and kin from an attacker, his goal is not durability but some form of
justice, no?
Troy Camplin:
I want institutions in place that increase the durability of a society of
liberty, and so should anyone who wants a society of liberty. That's precisely
how you achieve the goals of increasing liberty, by finding and perpetuating
those institutions that increase liberty in any given society.
And yes,
there are plenty of transient things. Bubbles, for example. Yes, transience
means a degree of durability. But if you told someone that a chair you had was
durable, and it broke when they sat in it, they would be justifiably angry with
you if you presented them with the argument that 10 minutes was an example of
durability.
If someone attacks me, my intention is pretty much nothing
but my continued durability. I won't be thinking about the justice or injustice
of what's happening at all. I'll be concerned with survival. I'll make the
arguments for justice when I have the luxury to do so.
Roger Bissell:
Three points about this last post of yours, Troy (though, contra the old-time
comedian, Jack E. Leonard, I certainly hope it wasn't your last one). ;)
1. I take the liberty to be worth pursuing and institutionalizing to be not a
quantitative thing, but a qualitative thing. In crudest terms, it would not be
legitimate to allow there to be a dictator who forced everyone to be free. That
would be, if not contradictory, at least hard to imagine how it could be put
into effect. But more generally, any utilitarian argument for maximizing liberty
has to confront the question of the MEANS by which liberty is maximized. IMO, as
long as individual freedom is increased, I don't care if someone lies or behaves
dependently or unfairly toward others in the course of doing it. But I do care
when it is argued that trade-offs of liberties are advocated in order to achieve
some other purported liberty. Probably no one here would sacrifice liberty for
security or social equality or social justice. But these days, the boundaries
don't seem as clear-cut as they used to
2. Regarding transience, what
you're saying, Troy, is that durability is contextual. I agree. The chair
example is a good one.
3. Your point about "continued durability" aka
survival is a very important one. IMO, ethical principles should be for the
purpose of helping us to live and be happy, and any principle that is rigidly
applied in a way that works AGAINST your survival is being used OUT OF CONTEXT
(of what moral principles are for).
One of the great benefits of living
in a society is when that society recognizes everyone's right to take the
actions necessary for their survival. Usually, we say, "so long as those actions
do not require violating someone else's equal freedom." But what about
situations where your continued survival is IMPOSSIBLE without, say, "borrowing"
your neighbor's car to get your seriously wounded loved one to the hospital? If
there are other options open to you, then sure, you can be morally required to
refrain from it. But then it's not necessary, just sufficient.
My
perspective is that you CANNOT be morally required to abstain from an action
that is not merely sufficient, but necessary for your survival. Such
circumstances rarely happen, which is why stable societies can be formed around
the principle of individual rights and can morally require us to refrain from
violating someone else's equal freedom. But when, in the course of human events,
we have not a normal social environment, but a true emergency situation, I
suggest that the context for rights at least temporarily does not exist.
Obviously, the goal is to get back to normal as quickly and painlessly as
possible. But if we are holding that CONTEXT MATTERS, then I suggest this
applies to rights as well, and in particular to the question of what is
necessary for human survival, which is what ethics and rights are supposed to
fundamentally be about. [This perspective has in past times been referred to as
"disappearing rights," and I would really enjoy hearing some vigorous discussion
of its merits or lack of same.]
This last issue may have some obscure
relevance to our current social-medical situation. ;-)
Troy Camplin:
In other words, there are bound to be times when it's easier to ask forgiveness
than permission. And for those who don't ask forgiveness, there are the courts.
Roger Bissell:
Troy Camplin, Good way to put it. I agree.
Troy Camplin:
BTW, my comments above about the relationship between virtue and beauty applies
to justice as well. After all, to be just is to be fair, and to be fair is to be
beautiful.
Robert L Campbell:
Troy Camplin, You're referring to "rules" in an extremely broad sense. What's
your notion of a rule? (If it's all laid out in Diaphysics, just say
so---I've ordered the book.)
Troy Camplin:
A rule is anything that guides an action, behavior, or interaction. They can
range from the laws of physics that can literally be neither bent nor broken, to
my choices of rules to write a poem (iambic pentameter, or not; a rhyme scheme,
or not; a given form, or not).
The vast majority of human activities can
be understood as games. Games have rules and they have fields of play (game
boards, etc.). This is why game theory is useful in understanding social
interactions, including economics. Still, much work needs to be done on how
actual rules result in actual actions in actual social situations, including how
different combinations of rules give rise to different outcomes.
Different rules give rise to different games. Chess and checkers are both played
on the same board, meaning there is a degree of rule similarity between the two
games. However, different pieces and different rules create considerably
different games, with chess being an unsolvable game, while checkers has already
been solved. It is possible to change the rules of chess to make is solvable,
but that would simplify the game and make it a less interesting game.
I
have made the argument that chess is a "better" game than checkers precisely
because the former is more complex and unsolvable. Yet, I have had checkers
players insist checkers is better. Of course, in a certain sense chess is hardly
better than checkers, since we are really comparing two different games with
different rules. Both are good games, as demonstrated by the popularity of each.
The insistence of checkers players who don't know how to play chess that
checkers is a better game points to a fact about human nature. People who have
mastered a game will defend that game. They will defend that game against any
kind of rule change that might "improve" the game.
The question is, what
do you do with rules?
There are four kinds of people: conformists who
play by the rules, rebels, nihilists, and tricksters. Any given person is likely
to have some combination, depending on the rules in question.
Are you a
nihilist? Are you a trickster god?
You're probably neither one.
You either play by the given rules or rebel against the rules. Both kinds of
people acknowledge the power and legitimacy of the rules. Both work to reinforce
and strengthen all the rules.
But suppose you come to understand that all
the rules could have been other than they are. Yes, all of them. And may yet be.
Some rules have great duration--the laws of physics, chemistry, and biology, in
decreasing duration--even the evolved psychology of humans has great duration,
such that we work best in certain social rules that themselves could have been
other than they are, but now must be as they are, given our evolved
psychologies. We as human beings are not going to change any of these, though
through cosmological evolution, some of these rules could still be other than
they are. Or they may have given rise to another set of rules that are much more
changeable. See the varieties of languages, foods, poetries in all our varied
cultures. Rules that could be otherwise, and have once been.
How, then,
do you respond?
Despair? Contempt of the rules? That's nihilism.
Joy? Appreciation of what the rules can do even while knowing they can change?
Then you're a trickster.
We know the nihilists. Sad-sack whiners who bomb
to bomb, destroy to destroy, despair because nothing matters or has meaning.
But he tricksters are those challenging the rules because they're rules,
using them when they're useful, ignoring them when they're not, building new
things, dancing our of love of life, joyful in meaning-creation and
making-matter.
The nihilist is serious about everything and appreciates
nothing.
The trickster appreciates everything and is serious about
nothing.
The trickster is bound to ridicule the binds you place upon
yourself. The trickster is bound to ridicule you if you seek to tighten all the
binds of others. He ridicules your cruelty and misanthropy.
He laughs at
autocrats and nihilists alike.
He laughs because he knows you could be
free.
Robert L Campbell:
Troy Camplin, I had a feeling you were giving rules an extremely broad
definition. "A rule is anything that guides an action, behavior, or
interaction." Does it matter whether it is possible for the system that engages
in rule-governed behavior to know explicitly what the rules are? Systems that
are subject to physical laws are usually not able come to know what any of these
laws are (human beings are a noteworthy exception). When I taught moral
development, I used to distinguish virtue ethics (such as Aristotle's) from
rule-based conceptions of ethics (such as Kant's, or Piaget's). Piaget was so
invested in rules that the first fourth of The Moral Judgment of the Child
is about children's ability to play marbles by the rules that prevail locally,
and their conscious understanding of those rules. But if I've acquired what
Aristotle considered to be the right habits, when I act according to habit I
will still be following a rule, because something will be guiding my behavior.
Troy Camplin:
I would say that even in humans, there are many, many, many rules we follow that
we do not explicitly know (any there's many, many more rules we've only recently
articulated, and which are still really only known by a small set of experts).
We followed the laws of physics well before anyone articulated them. Human-made
laws and rules are really nothing more than special cases of the various laws
and rules of nature.
Robert L Campbell:
Troy Camplin, On your view, how do rules emerge? It seems as though (some?)
rules must always be there.
Troy Camplin:
They emerge through interactions. Those interactions that result in something
stable remain in place, held in place by the emergent structures.
Joel Schlosberg:
Chris Matthew Sciabarra, I gotta admit that I've missed your input this week...
being such a veteran of academic Marxism gives your work a different flavor than
most libertarians for whom they are the enemy, but I particularly wanted to hear
what you had to say about Marxists being capable only of "mere mindless
following and undifferentiated behavior"! Besides their ample capacity for
internecine sectarianism (as Murray Rothbard noted in "The Myth of Monolithic
Communism" Marxists have no more reason to agree on applying their common
ideology than Christians have), that seems like a harsh assessment, given the
creative innovations of talented individual minds in the Soviet Union, from the
AK-47 to Shostakovich's symphonies to Tetris.
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
Joel Schlosberg - Let me just say that like libertarians, Marxists are certainly
not a monolithic bunch (and if one broadens that to "socialists"... it is
waaaaaaay NOT a monolithic bunch!). Personally, I don't think one could even
remotely characterize the Soviet Union as a Marxist state. Perhaps one might
characterize it as "Marxist-Leninist" state socialism---but it had nothing to do
with Marx's vision of socialism or communism. The Soviet Union emerged from an
essentially feudal 'materialist' base rather than the advanced capitalist
material conditions that Marx insisted were essential to the creation of a
socialist society, one that would have resolved the problem of scarcity and made
possible distribution "from each according to his ability to each according to
his needs."
I think that one could make an argument for a more "humanist"
and even neo-Aristotelian Marx, but I don't think that this aspect of Marx's
work is the target of Troy's critique. I think Troy is offering an alternative
"dialectical materialist" take that provocatively turns Marx on his head, in a
way that Marx claimed to have turned Hegel on his head. One can agree or
disagree with Troy's dialectical materialist approach, but we (the co-editors of
the anthology) found it a most provocative addition to the volume insofar as it
challenged both libertarian and Marxist views of dialectical materialism
and its implications.
Troy Camplin:
Nothing like using a person's ideas against their own ideas. But then, my
dissertation committee chair used deconstruction against Derrida, so I suppose
one could say I learned that lesson well.
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
Troy Camplin - Sounds familiar. ;) Bertell Ollman, my thesis advisor and
long-time friend, could probably say a few things about this, were he a member
of this study group.
Joel Schlosberg:
We could use a few good Marxists! If only to tell us if we're understanding the
ideas we're turning against them ;)
Milton Friedman is nobody's idea of a Marxist but I came across a quote in which
he sounds dialectical: "the problem is not that bureaucrats are bad people. The
problem, as the Marxists would say, is with the system, not with the people. The
self-interest of people in government leads them to behave in a way that is
against the self-interest of the rest of us." And Kevin Carson is fond of the
phrase "Destroying the Master's House With the Master's Tools" (the title of one
of his C4SS papers, but also used in various forms elsewhere), and he's tried to
get anti-capitalists to take the intellectual tools of free-market capitalist
ideology more seriously rather than just dismissing them as apologias for greed.
Joel Schlosberg:
Chris, I am a bit surprised you point to the lack of "advanced capitalist
material conditions that Marx insisted were essential to the creation of a
socialist society" as the main reason for the USSR's failure, since that would
seem to harken back to the most rigidly historically determinist versions of
mid-20th century Marxism! (Ones that failed to take into account the wave of
movements that applied Bakuninist strategies to overthrow feudal regimes in the
third world, even if their Leninist ideologies prevented them from becoming a
more liberating alternative, while ones in the industrialized first world became
increasingly reformist.) And as Kevin Carson noted on last week's thread, just
as his followers were becoming increasingly convinced that brute-force
industrialization was a necessary transitional stage, "Marx was investigating
the potential of the Russian Mir and other precapitalist institutions as
vehicles for leapfrogging directly to socialism without actually going through
the process of primitive accumulation that W[estern] Europe did." Kevin asked
where his quote about the dialectic being commonly misunderstood as "a
historical process divided into neat stages with nobody coloring outside the
lines" is from, the source is this blog post, which was one that helped
introduce me to a certain dialectical-Ayn Randian scholar:
http://mutualist.blogspot.com/2005/02/dialogue-continues.html
Troy Camplin: There probably is something to the fact that Marxism has mostly been tried by superimposing it into feudalist political structures rather than onto advanced economies. Or has it? https://medium.com/@troycamplin/i-recently-wrote-a-piece-arguing-that-the-united-states-because-of-the-existence-of-property-taxes-3da6bea98cc9
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
Joel Schlosberg - I don't think I was saying that the reason that the Soviet
Union failed was *because* it didn't follow Marx's historical materialist view
of history. And Kevin Carson is surely correct that Marx did indeed investigate
the idea of "leap-frogging" (and that's a fine piece by Kevin!).
But I
do think that one of the essential ingredients in Marx's view of a future
communism was his investment in the idea of a post-scarcity society. The full
implementation of the mantra, 'from each according to his ability to each
according to his needs', was simply not possible without a society that had
created such an abundance of goods so as to, essentially, solve the problem of
scarcity. Marx recognized the highly progressive nature of capitalism as a mode
of production, far superior to previous modes of production, and saw it as a
transformative engine that could develop the forces of production in such a way
as to make that abundance possible---while sewing within it the seeds of its own
destruction and of a newer, more progressive alternative in socialism (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/From_each_according_to_his_ability,_to_each_according_to_his_needs)
I would highly recommend an essay by Bertell Ollman on this, who argues that
every form of socialism that is emergent must take into account the historical
and material conditions that exist in any particular society; check out "Communism:
Ours, Not Theirs".
Joel Schlosberg:
Those ten points in the Communist Manifesto weren't intended to be an end goal
to communism---as Chris's comrade/thesis-advisor points out, calling for "a
heavy progressive or graduated income tax" implies that "significant differences
of income still exist"! (And as Erich Fromm noted, that "most of its demands are
fulfilled in a number of capitalist countries" could be taken as evidence that
they are "exceedingly modest").
https://www.nyu.edu/projects/ollman/docs/marxs_vision.php
Troy Camplin:
In the end, the entrepreneurs will always undermine Marxism. Even if we "solved"
the problem of scarcity for all currently-existing products, some jerk would
come along and invent something new, and there would, again, be a shortage---of
that new product!
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
Troy Camplin - And the bottom-line issue is that even in a society of abundance,
there is always, as the Austrians (especially Rothbard) pointed out, the
scarcity of time. Even if people receive according to their needs, each person's
needs (which are not static) -- and values -- are "agent-relative" within a
time-dimension that is not eternal. So the satisfaction of needs must still take
place within the context of scarce time, in which not every evolving "need" can
possibly be filled.
Trotsky's view of a new communist man (an extension
of many utopian ideals in Russian thought) is a constructivist one, even if it
is "contextualized" by future "conditions" that make such an achievement
possible. That view was best expressed in his statement that in the future
communist society, "Man will become immeasurably stronger, wiser and subtler;
his body will become more harmonized, his movements more rhythmic, his voice
more musical. The forms of life will become dynamically dramatic. The average
human type will rise to the heights of an Aristotle, a Goethe, or a Marx. And
above this ridge new peaks will rise." (https://www.marxists.org/archive/trotsky/1924/lit_revo/ch08.htm)
There are some parallels here with Rand's own projection of the ideal man, who
unites the businessman and the intellectual, theory and practice, for whom
values, purpose, and action are integrated. (I compare this Randian notion to
those that can be found in Russian Symbolism and in the Russian Silver Age of
her youth, in my book, Ayn Rand: The Russian Radical (see especially the
section, "God Builder?", in Chapter 13, "History and Resolution", pp. 349-352).
Joel Schlosberg: Would voluntary communism on a small scale not count as "full implementation" because it wasn't society-wide, or not "abundant" enough even if it is based on generosity (which it seems is if anything more likely to occur among those who share to make do with little as those who can accumulate more for themselves)? I don't think anyone would count Walter Block as more of a Marxist than Bertell Ollman, but he has noted that "the typical nuclear family, moreover, is a (voluntary) socialist commune! All members of the family consume not in accordance with their ability to earn, but based on their needs. The parents may earn the entire income, but certainly do not consume it all; the (young) children earn none of it, but consume on the basis of their needs." http://www.walterblock.com/wp-content/uploads/publications/libertarian_perspective_policical_economy.pdf
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
Joel Schlosberg - Here it comes -- I think it depends upon the context. And we
will have a few upcoming chapters that touch upon the idea of labor-managed
enterprises, within different institutional contexts, especially the
contribution written by DOL member, Dave Prychitko. So lots more to come on
this...
Troy Camplin:
Chris, I was trying to be a little generous to Marx. ;-)
Joel, I heard
Walter Williams make the same argument about 30 years ago, about the family
being fundamentally Marxist in structure. As Williams observed, Marxism works,
so long as you can keep up with the names.
Joel Schlosberg:
Chris, you're saying that you prefer "a Marxism which is developed in a concrete
social context; which is flexible, open and unafraid to re-think its
revolutionary perspectives according to specific conditions; and which fashions
its language as a means of communication, analysis and mobilization, rather than
employing it merely as ritualistic invocation" rather than "Marxism of the
hand-me-down variety, where an ideological perspective and vocabulary developed
in a different epoch or a different political-cultural environment is transposed
whole and adopted as an all-embracing wisdom"?
https://books.google.com/books?id=0WQQRZJsjzkC&pg=PA137
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
Joel Schlosberg - Well, now, don't put words in my mouth! I'm just saying that I
think Ollman's essay has a lot of validity to it, in terms of how Marx's
approach differed from that offered by both Marxist-Leninists in the Russian
context and that offered by the typical utopian socialists. And the key
difference, for Ollman, lies in the dialectical way in which Marx approached the
question of socialism -- something that, for Marx, had to emerge from a specific
context, a context that had to be fully understood in order to be transcended.
Troy Camplin:
And that's kind of the point of my linked essay. Marxism mapped onto Feudalist
Russia gave us the Soviet Union, while Marxism mapped onto the U.S. gave us the
contemporary welfare state (though the "heavily graduated income tax" isn't so
heavily graduated, given we learned you get better revenues from a less
graduated one).
Jason Walker:
Troy: On the whole, I very much enjoyed this discussion. For the moment, I don't
know that I have a decisive critique or it or anything, beyond a perhaps
stylistic observation, and a methodological worry. On the former, this may just
reflect my training in analytic styles of philosophy, but it seemed very ...
peripatetic, for want of a better description. "All over the place" might be a
more informal way of putting it. That's not necessarily a bug or a feature; just
an observation that seems less about, in analytic style, rigorously identifying
and defending a primary thesis, and more about giving a general lay of the land
from place to place. It's like you're giving the reader a grand tour of your
dialectical laboratory: here's where you keep the lungfish, notice this cool
thing about them, here are the gobies, here's the ritualized sacrifice, here's
the shameful ape, the fractals are over there, and the centerpiece of my
collection, the territory-holding males! I wonder if my difficulties processing
this aren't like the androids of Season 1 of Westworld, who can't recognize
artifacts from outside their park.
As for the methodological worry, it's
this. Yours is not the first attempt I've seen to take concepts from metaphysics
or epistemology, and read them into the sciences. I'm not going to say you're
wrong to make these observations; in fact, I find myself sympathetic with your
big picture here. It's more that you may be demanding too much of the concept,
as if you're wanting dialectics to serve as a unified field theory of sorts,
tying almost everything together, from the behavior of atoms to biological
evolution to human ritual and political/economic theory. One certainly can't
accuse you of lacking ambition here.
The two difficulties this may pose
are these. First, I'd very much want to know to what degree specialists in these
fields would consent to this framework being used to describe what they do. I've
learned to be wary of stepping on the toes of specialists in other fields, both
out of respect for their own years of study and careful scholarship, and more
importantly, out of a frank acknowledgment of my own relative ignorance. I've
appreciated the legal scholarship of Richard Epstein, but when he tried to dip
his toe into epidemiology this last month, that kind of blew up in his face.
When my work goes into interdisciplinary directions, I find that I rely very
heavily on literature from those other disciplines, citing those works, and
using the concepts and descriptions *from those disciplines* to illustrate or
describe whatever point I'm raising. For example, in my dissertation, I wanted
to make it clear that the notion of emergent order was not a novelty. Perhaps it
was counter-intuitive in the domain where I located it (legal order), but it can
be found in biological evolution, neuroscience and of course economics. But I
would be adverse to tell the biologist, neuroscientist or economist that they
ought to use the framing I use in my own work, or that my framing in any sense
supersedes theirs. I'm not sure that's what you're doing or even intending to
do, but I suppose that's why I'm characterizing this as a methodological worry
rather than a criticism.
Second, there's the conceptual inflation
problem. The inflation of currency certainly is one way to illustrate the
problem, but as a huge fan of South Park, I'd like to invoke the aliens
who appear in the classic episode, "Starvin' Marvin in Space." The titular
Marvin discovers a downed alien craft, which whisks him away to an alien world
called Marklar. The aliens speak to Marvin in English, but an oddity about this
species is that nearly every noun in their language is "Marklar," as well as
every proper name for every member of their group. It's played for laughs, this
being South Park and all, but I've always liked the way it illustrates
the practical problem of a single term being used for too many distinct kinds.
Dialectics is useful for the epistemologist and for other philosophers as well,
but I'm not sure how useful the concept remains if we want to say that it's the
same thing concept that captures what the anthropologist, the chemist, the
astrophysicist, et al., are doing, anymore that calling it all Marklar would be
a useful framing.
Troy Camplin:
I suppose some background about me would help to answer some of your questions.
I have a B.A. in recombinant gene technology, meaning I've taken classes in
physics, chemistry, and biology, with an emphasis, obviously, on molecular
biology. I did two years of graduate work in molecular biology before getting
bored and deciding to get a Master's in English so I could be a fiction writer.
I have a Ph.D. in the arts and humanities, and in my
dissertation
I talk about the neurological bases of beauty and artistic creation. One of the
people on my dissertation committee had two Ph.D.s, one in biology and one in
English--and she had no objections to my dissertation (neither did the
neuroscientists another on my committee slipped the neuroscience part to). I was
also reading a great deal of philosophy and economics during these times, and
this led to my having several peer reviewed pieces on economics and spontaneous
order theory, including a book chapter in a collection on the psychological
theories of F.A. Hayek. In other words, I'm enough of an autodidact in economics
to get publications in the field, and I've had more than a few economists
compliment me on the fact that I "think like an economist."
The long and
short of it is, I am an interdisciplinary thinker and scholar because that's how
I've educated myself, formally (mostly) and informally, with most of my peer
reviewed publications in what I've informally educated myself in. I have
absolute confidence that anyone in any field about which I write would at least
say that I understand their field.
The thing I do very well is find
patterns, especially complex patterns. I've had people in various fields be
surprised that I saw a pattern in their field that existed in other fields--and,
most importantly, they didn't deny its existence.
As for your final
point, one could make the argument that such sound patterns as German, English,
French, Swahili, Cantonese, Japanese, Arabic, Hopi, Aztec, Wari, Hawaiian, and
so on are so different that we shouldn't call them all by one word. But I think
it's very useful to call them all "language," and to study them all under a
single rubric. The existence of variations on a theme doesn't mean the theme
doesn't exist. This is the mistake people who denied there is such a thing as
"human nature" made. If you focus only on the differences, you won't understand
how things are related to each other. One of course shouldn't go in the opposite
direction and insist that everything is just One Thing, as the monists would
have it, either. It's really both-and. It's unity in variety and variety in
unity, with different levels of complexity giving rise to different entities
with different behaviors, but which nevertheless do have some structural
commonalities. I espouse a poststructuralist structuralism, a set of common
rules that run through the various levels of complexity and which in turn give
rise to ever-greater complexity in the cosmos, where the unity gives rise to
variety, where truth and ideas and concepts are the absent centers of the
actually-existent.
Roger Bissell:
Jason & Troy: I have a similar concern about "concept inflation." Not just about
extending "dialectics" down into botany (let alone atomic physics!) - but also
about other important concepts like "logic" (Hegel and I think Plato wanted to
make logic metaphysical, rather than just a process/method of cognition and
interaction by certain conscious beings) and "intentionality" (the "aboutness"
of consciousness, which some want to extend to the tendency of atoms to relate
to one another in physical and chemical bonds).
On the other hand, I'm
one of the apparent minority of people who maintain that "final causation" is
not just restricted to living (let alone conscious) beings, but to EVERY process
in the universe. There is a subcategory of final causes or "ends" that pertain
to biology, but ANY result, anything determined by the identity of the thing(s)
acting or interacting, is an "end" in that sense. Perhaps this shouldn't be
included in "teleology" - or perhaps, instead, "teleology" should be expanded to
include both the ends of organic life forms and the ends/necessary results of
inorganic entity processes.
Troy Camplin:
Marx was the one to extend dialectics with dialectical materialism. I just took
him seriously--and farther, as a result.
Nietzsche proposed the
Apollonian and Dionysian as ways to understand the arts. Music and Lyrical
poetry were Dionysian, Epic poetry and sculpture were Apollonian, and Tragedy
was the synthesis of the two. However, Nietzsche observed that these are really
aspects of the cosmos itself, which we are tapping into in the production of
certain kinds of art.
Dialectical thinking is precisely this. It's
tapping into the way the cosmos itself is constructed and how things come about
in the first place. We are merely recognizing it and making use of it in our own
thinking. We are thus becoming more like the cosmos as a whole by engaging in
the very processes underlying every aspect of reality.
Every organism
has a telos. The embryo develops into the mature organism, and then there is a
falling off. Such things as final causes are properly applied to any process in
which there can be a mature form and a falling off from that form.
I
understand the concern about over-extension. It's not uncommon to find a
metaphor and run with it and apply it to everything. One must approach these
things with caution. That being said, one must not then over-extend THAT and
reject the possibility that there are common patterns to be found in all levels
of reality in the cosmos, from the quantum physical through the human social
environments. Understanding what those patterns are will help us to understand
the cosmos as a whole--and be able to very quickly learn about each area of
knowledge we use to study each level of complexity in the cosmos. Once you have
the structures down, the rest is details.
Robert L Campbell:
Troy Camplin Again, this may all be covered in Diaphysics, whose arrival
I eagerly await. I'll ask anyway: How would you contrast your project with
Herbert Spencer's?
Troy Camplin:
Perhaps not dissimilar, though hopefully much more informed by more recent
information. :-)
Roger Bissell:
RAND, NIETZSCHE, AND APOLLO
A few years ago, I took issue with Rand's
characterization of the Apollo/Dionysus polarity that she claimed to find in
Nietzsche. (See "Will the Real Apollo Please Stand Up? Rand, Nietzsche, and the
Reason-Emotion Dichotomy" in The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies, volume 10,
no. 2 (Spring 2009): 343-69.) Rand sometimes spoke of "man worship," but she
could just as easily be seen as advocating Apollo worship. She was unequivocal
about this. To her, Apollo was the God of Reason, while Dionysus was the God of
Wine and of the wilder emotions. [See her 1970 essay, "Apollo vs. Dionysus,"
Return of the Primitive: The Anti-Industrial Revolution. (Formerly The
New Left: The Anti-Industrial Revolution). New expanded version edited by
Peter Schwartz. New York: Meridian.]
Of course, the veneration or
emulation of Apollo is more widespread than that Rand and her followers. It is
also found among many who fancy themselves to be more in the refined,
emotionally restrained, tradition-respecting "Classical" mode. (Yes, these two
groups are at odds, since Rand et al favor the "Romantic," going to great
lengths to characterize it as the school of "volition" and thus the school of
"reason." To her, the pastel, timid, stuffy Classical style was not rational in
any sense important to her as a champion of reason used as the primary tool of
the passionate and heroic life.)
In my opinion, this is both a misreading
of Nietzsche, as well as a failure to understand Apollo's original status and
role in Greek culture. Some say that Nietzsche was betraying the rational
Apollonian element in embracing the irrational Dionysian element, but I think it
more likely that Nietzsche simply did not view Apollo as purely rational (as
Rand and the wider traditional interpretation take him to be, each in their
different ways). Instead, I think there are seeds within Nietzsche's portrait of
Apollo that point toward an entirely different characterization of him. Consider
this from Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy:
This joyous necessity of the dream experience has been embodied by the Greeks in
their Apollo: Apollo, the god of all plastic energies, is at the same time
the soothsaying god. He, who (as the
etymology of the name indicates) is the 'shining one,' the deity of light, is
also ruler over the beautiful illusion of the inner world of fantasy. . . .
[T]his deep consciousness of nature, healing and helping in sleep and dreams, is
at the same time the symbolical analogue of the soothsaying faculty and of the
arts generally, which make life possible and worth living. (emphasis added)
Soothsaying and dreams, which are virtually signature attributes of Apollo, are
not rational activities. In fact, in Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy, the
function of reason is, in fact, represented not by Apollo, but by . . . wait for
it Socrates and his dialectic!!
In light of the characterizations
presented in ancient Greek mythology, Rand's portrait of Apollo is also somewhat
askew. Apollo is identified variously as the god of prophecy, music, poetry,
mathematics (he was believed to be the father of Pythagoras), medicine (his son
Asclepius was the god of medicine), archery, light, the sun, streets and
highways, colonization, order, justice, and legality, flocks and crops, plagues,
and (perhaps) wolves and mice.
There are only two items in this list that
might justify attributing "god of reason" to Apollo. One is his sponsorship of
music by the lyre and the kithara, which was very well-ordered (and thus
"rational") compared to the more unruly, ecstatic rhythms of the aulos and drums
in the music nurtured by Dionysus. The other is in his tendency to break up
fights and to punish wrong doers, as well as to refrain from joining in the
frivolous fighting that his father Zeus fomented, as reported in the Iliad.
To the ancient Greeks, as a matter of fact, Apollo was not primarily regarded as
a "god of reason." In fact, he was just as much a patron of the arts as he was
of the sciences. To see this, one need only look at the array of subjects
attached to his wards, the Muses: epic poetry, history, mime, the flute, light
verse and dance, lyric choral poetry, tragedy, comedy, and astronomy. Such a
disparate nonet defies a simple, unitary explanation in terms of the interests
of a "god of reason."
By contrast, it was Athena who was explicitly
identified as the goddess of reason and intelligence, as well as the city,
agriculture, handicrafts, arts and literature, and she is credited with numerous
inventions, including the bridle, the pot, the flute, the trumpet, the rake, the
plow, the ship, the chariot, and the yoke. [We might ask: Why didn't Rand ever
credit Athena for this? Might it be related to her idiosyncratic belief that a
woman should not be President?] It has also been noted that the current St.
Peter's Cathedral in Rome features Minerva (Goddess of Reason) on the side of
rational thinkers, and Apollo (God of Poetry) on side of inspirational thinkers.
Unless it were somehow argued that "reason" is a broader concept than
"rational thinking," and that it subsumes both "rational thinking" and
"inspirational thinking" (and poetry), it would seem that, yet again, we have a
clear sign that Western civilization regarded the Apollonian as being, if not
completely irrational, at least not essentially rational.
Yes, in light
of Apollo's sponsorship of the Muses for subjects like astronomy and
mathematics, he can arguably be seen as pro-thinking and pro-reason, at least in
some respects. On the other hand, in light of Apollo's sponsorship of the Muses
for subjects like music and poetry, he should perhaps instead be seen as
pro-feeling and pro-intuition.
Rand's view implies that Apollo, in
symbolizing reason, was against both the Dionysian antirational focus on
feelings and the apparently Apollonian anti-rational reliance on mystic
intuition (the basis of prophecy and divination, Apollo's watchword). Arrowsmith
writes, however:
Apollo . . . is not simply a god of reason. Not unless one possesses, as the
Greeks did, a sense of reason so ample that discursive logic, lyric poetry,
music, and prophecy---but above all, prophecy---are, all of them, wholly
rational activities, i.e., activities of the whole mind, thought literally
infused with feeling. (emphasis added) [Editor's foreword in Sophocles 1978.
Oedipus the King. Edited by Stephen Berg and Diskin Clay. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.]
In effect, then, we must build a new characterization of Apollo, somewhat
similar to, but different in critical ways from, the perspective of Rand---and
more akin, actually, to the perspective of Nietzsche.
Rather than Apollo
and Dionysus---half-brothers, sired by the omnipresent and apparently
omni-potent Zeus---being polar opposites, as Rand depicts them, Apollo is an
introverted intuitive type, in parallel to the extraverted sensing type of
Apollo's earthier, but no more experience-driven half-brother, Dionysus.
Nietzsche recognized this fundamental experiential passion in Apollonians:
If we could imagine dissonance become man---and what else is man?---this
dissonance, to be able to live, would need a splendid illusion that would cover
dissonance with a veil of beauty. This is the true artistic aim of Apollo in
whose name we comprehend all those countless illusions of the beauty of mere
appearance that at every moment make life worth living at all and prompt the
desire to live on in order to experience the next moment. (emphasis added)
So, according to Nietzsche, man has a survival need to deliberately create
beautiful illusions with which to cover or disguise the dissonance in life, and
Apollo's "true artistic aim" is to provide such experiences that "at every
moment make life worth living at all and prompt the desire to live on in order
to experience the next moment."
This is hardly Rand's view of Apollo or
of art! Indeed, she might well regard such a view as irrational. More
importantly, though, it hardly serves to portray Apollo as quintessentially
rational, but instead as more centrally concerned with experiential
enjoyment---specifically, with the pursuit of artistic and scientific happiness.
Most deeply, both Apollonians and Dionysians are drawn to "flow"
experiences, and they completely immerse themselves in their respective
preferred kinds of process, whether meditation, creativity, worship, etc., or
sports, crafts, sexuality, etc. Thus, Apollonians are, in a very general way,
very much like the Dionysians in their pursuit of experiential ecstasy, only on
a more abstract or spiritual plane.
Further, Apollo was well known to
have been the sponsor of the nine Muses, who presided over not just a number of
the arts, but also mathematics and astronomy, points to an appropriate parallel
label we might apply to the Apollonians: the "Muse-Seeker." Clearly, the
Apollonian orientation is an abstract-level focus on creative discovery in
various different realms, which is reached by following one's muse, as it were.
For this reason, I have coined the term "Muse-Seeker," which I think well
captures the spirit of Apollo as the pursuit not of one's physical or sensuous
impulses (as do the Dionysians), but, on the parallel, abstract plane of
experience, of one's spiritual, aesthetic, and intellectual inspirations.
The essence of the Apollonian temperament is thus neither reason (thinking)
nor emotion (feeling), but intuition. Furthermore, it is not intuition in
general, but specifically extraverted intuition, the kind of intuition
that looks out at the world and finds inspiration in nature and human society
and creates a coherent inner model, whether harmonious or logical. Extraverted
intuition is a process of exploring the world, seeing possible connections, and
exercising creative invention, whether artistic or theoretical, on what one
encounters.
The Apollonian exercise of extraverted intuition, which
stresses theoretical or artistic breadth, while the Promethean use of
introverted intuition emphasizes conceptual or abstract depth or hierarchy.
Apollonian extraverted intuition places a premium on coherence or "horizontal"
integration, on finding a conceptual or artistic integration of data or
ideas---while Promethean introverted intuition strives most strongly for
correspondence to reality or "vertical" integration, on justifying one's
conceptual or artistic integrations. For instance, a process of extraverted
intuition is what yields the realization that the regularity of a pendulum's
swing and the arc of a projectile's motion both display certain regular
patterns, while a process of introverted intuition is what yields the
realization that both kinds of motion are governed by the same underlying causal
principle. In this respect, Galileo and Kepler were more Apollonian, while
Newton was more Promethean.
Apollo has been done a disservice by the
long-lived tug-of-war between the partisans of the reason-emotion dichotomy.
Apollo is not, as Rand claims, the god of reason, guiding us in the preserving
or building or mastering of nature. Instead, Apollo is all about understanding
and exploring and discovering what makes the human race and the universe tick.
He is the quintessential hunter-gatherer of the spirit, i.e., of Truth and
Goodness and Beauty. As a consequence, the person of Apollonian temperament
embraces either reason or emotion, as appropriate, in his quest to seek and
nurture his muse. His god, Apollo, is the god of (extraverted) intuition. This
is the real Apollo.
[Note to readers: this is a radically abbreviated
version of my JARS essay. I invite those wanting to read the full version to
download it from the Penn State University Press web site].
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
It is actually available on JSTOR
here.
Troy Camplin:
The only proper answer:
God and Goddess
The moon is goddess of all
poetry---
Except the poetry of Greece---the sun,
Apollo, stands surrounded
by the Muses---
His is a poetry no light shall shun.
In other realms
the darkness rules the verse,
The poet hides in shadows, hides in lies---
Apollo shines the sun of truth through lines
And in his wisdom everything
defies.
Apollo's poetry is prophesy---
The future speaking to the now
in rhyme---
It brings enlightenment and its warm glow
Will bring the mind
beauty's fullness in time.
The Muses' poetry is Memory---
Plurality of
knowledge--and sets loose
Great wisdom to make beautiful---
Such is the
power of their father, Zeus.
But do not think the virgin goddess dim---
She finds her way into our rhyme and verse---
Without her you cannot give
birth, your lines
Will be stillborn, delivered in a hearse.
Living
Classicism
I traveled once to Greece, the ancient land
Of tragedy,
philosophy, the gods---
And there, beneath the plane tree I would stand,
Escape Apollo's heat, take Plato's nods.
In Athens in the paths of
Socrates
I walked--agora and the marketplace
Today where women sell their
wares. I'd seize
The very air, the ancient time and space.
In Naxos
where Apollo's gate still stands,
Where Zeus hid Dionysus in a cave,
I ate
in mountaintop cafes, my hands
Felt marble mountains---Naxos I still crave.
In Delphi where the oracles would speak
Apollo's prophesies in vents now
sealed--
I stood within the theater to peak
At what great Dionysus once
revealed.
In Thassos where the ancient Greeks had sailed
From Naxos,
Dionysus first set shoot---
A dining archeologist regaled
Me with the
findings of this ancient root.
I lived in Greece a month, and there I
found
An understanding of the things I'd read---
And having traveled I
have found the ground
That grows the sweet figs that keep me well-fed.
The Triumph of Mercury
When Dionysus marched into the East
He met with Isis to unite the East
Apollo stayed at home in Rome, the West
Looked on, appalled that Bacchus
left the West
In decadence drunk Dionysus's feast
We've seen to weaken
all those in the East
And golden reason, virtue stood the test
That
war had woven all throughout the West
Yet, no one understood the fluid
beast,
The Proteus who's river of the East
While from the boot the
people deemed the best
Deep rivers full of blood shed in the West
The
satyrs on the islands have not ceased
To dance in orgy dreams throughout the
East
The Muses make the rhythms of the blest
And sculpt their golden
means throughout the West
The Maenads should be feared when they're
released
They'll rend and rip and rive across the East
There's none
august enough to wear the crest
So long rejected by men in the West
And wealth's complexified, slowly increased
As dawn is spreading all
throughout the East
Now Hermes will interpret all the East
And
synthesize it with the weary West
Dithyramb
Wake up! Be
alive! Have some fucking passion!
Why must we live a life where dead spirits
are the fashion?
Where are the spirits that make us want to dance?
Why
can't we touch and kiss, make romance
A fiery and wanton thing
That makes
us bellow out and sing
From our very visceral guts, buried down
So deep
our very memories of it have been drowned?
There is no Dionysian---and
Apollo's not the rule---
And every scholar, every fool
Who claims to know
the masked god's revelry
Is shown a Pentheus without chivalry---
An
infection of our lives and culture,
Lacking the taste of even a vulture.
There is no Dionysus in academic verse---
Throwing random words together so
only the worst
Are raised to the heights of academia---
Creating at best a
poetic bulimia.
So be gone, you culture killers, killers of the human soul,
You who have the vision of a naked mole
Rat digging through the desert sands,
Whose ignorant notions of freedom only tie the hands.
Be gone, you culture
killers, let be reborn
Dionysus with his goring bullish horn---
Dionysus
with great Apollo, his friend,
Making this dead culture bend
Until it
breaks up into something new
(Which is also old, full of life and the true).
It is time to wake up! Hear the siren call
Us up out of our beds until we
recall
To this new life our new-cherished memes---
All of the passion and
life of our dreams.
Roger Bissell:
Troy Camplin, Sounds Apollonian to me! Are you perchance a fellow Muse-Seeker?
;-)
Troy Camplin:
My lyrical poetry is as Dionysian as I can get, given my lack of musical
training. I do try to maintain the Apollonian-Dionysian balance in my tragic
plays, though---they're all in iambic pentameter, and could ostensibly be sung
and put to music.
Troy Camplin
BTW, my poetry is as peripatetic as my prose. I blame the influence of
Aristotle. .;-)
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
Troy Camplin - Meet Roger Bissell, musician, composer, arranger, and trombonist
extraordinaire! Perhaps the new George and Ira Gershwin will emerge from this
Study Group, just in time for Roger's chapter on the Great American Songbook! ;)
Troy Camplin:
Never know what kind of madness might emerge.
Joel Schlosberg:
Another Rand-influenced composer, who was a music student at NYU:
http://www.denvercasado.com/listen/
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
And ironically, I knew (and know) Denver very well! We also re-connected as FB
friends back in January 2019. Very nice guy!
Joel Schlosberg:
Rereading Leonard Peikoff's response to 9/11 (which was circulated by the
Objectivist club; I don't think they were as bloodthirsty, but the loudest
voices tended to predominate), I notice that aside from his general condemnation
of pointy-headed peaceniks who "are asking a reeling nation to show
neighbor-love by shunning 'vengeance'" (If you were in Theodore Sturgeon's
"Thunder and Roses", in which American survivors of a Soviet nuclear first
strike must decide whether or not to retaliate, you'd push the button, wouldn't
you Lenny?), there's also a swipe at "multiculturalists---rejecting the concept
of objectivity" who avoid "condemnation" of Arab culture. And I thought I might
have had an unnecessarily harsh take on Objectivist views of Arab cultures being
"dominated by tribalism and theocratic fanaticism" in back in the discussion of
Chapter 1!
http://ontology.buffalo.edu/smith/courses01/rrtw/Peikoff.pdf
Roger Bissell:
For some reason, Peikoff thought that our real enemy in the Middle East was
neither Iraq nor Saudi Arabia, but Iran, and he vociferously included nuclear
weapons in possible means of attacking them. He said we absolutely have the
moral right to use nuclear weapons on them, if that's the best strategic way to
change their regime. See this video interview by Bill O'Reilly (not sure of the
year, but probably 2002):
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=JoAWCwm-UXw
Chris Matthew Sciabarra:
Joel Schlosberg - At least with regard to that point made in Chapter One, that
would have been Rand's argument *against* nation-building and certainly against
a social "tabula rasa" (as I quoted Troy Camplin to that effect), such as the
one advocated by the nuclear nihilists among her most orthodox followers.
Roger Bissell:
Chris Matthew Sciabarra, Nihilists or annihilists? (Or is there even a
difference?) ;-)
Joel Schlosberg:
The actual capital-N Nihilists were no annihilists -- Kropotkin pointed out that
their destructive streak was focused on the repressive features of Tsarist
society (as the Cynics were on those of their ancient Greek society), and he and
Henry George noted their devotion to liberty.
Susan Love Brown:
Troy Camplin's "Aesthetics, Ritual, Property, and Fish" covers so much territory
(no pun intended) that it is difficult to know where to begin. It is difficult
to tailor comments to discuss all of the material here, so I will make a few
pointed comments from my perspective as a political and psychological
anthropologist, who also studies communalism, utopianism, and gender, among
other things. This essay suggests two things: (1) that humans recognize patterns
in nature and copy them artistically from direct observation; (2) dialectical
methodology is a function of human rationality/reason and is applied whether or
not the thinker is consciously aware of it as a methodology. Although all human
nature arises from their biology, biology cannot explain all human actions,
including that which takes place in the artistic domain. Art is inborn. We know
that art (drawing, painting, music, poetry) arises in every culture from
hunting/gathering bands to our own highly complex society, but its meaning
cannot be explained solely by its origins in the brain.
That said, here are some further points that I throw out for consideration.
1. "... we are a species of social mammal. To the degree that we are
individuals, we are individuated within our social contexts. And both are
constrained by our genetics. And that means, we are socially embedded
individuals who are individuated within each of our social contexts, which
itself necessarily interact with our genes and epigenetic patterns through our
plastic neurons" (p.337).
I agree that both individuality and sociality are aspects of human nature.
However, I also don't think you can reduce everything to biology or even
neurons. Any tensions that arise, arise because of particular configurations of
society and how the individual operates against its strictures. But these things
are no self-evident; we have to discover what principles exist and how they
operate. This can only be learned through trial and error. Biology in general
and neurosciences in particular can only explain the biological. Any
understanding of human action must engage the social and cultural levels of
existence. Individuality is a given of human nature, but the ideology of
individualism is not.
2. The author seems to confuse biological evolution and social evolution.
Evolution as a phenomenon and process can be seen among galaxies, species, and
human societies---the movement from simple to complex, movement from homogeneity
to heterogeneity. Nevertheless, these evolutions operate by different rules and
are not comparable beyond the description of the process itself. It reminds me
of Kroeber's distinction between the inorganic, organic, and superorganic. Each
of these requires different tools for understanding, and while they are
connected as they must be, they are not reducible to each other. Biological
evolution cannot lead to the institution of private property or individualism.
These are products of social evolution and the culture that arises with it.
3. "The emergence of ritual is a dialectical solution to the problem of
reproduction created by the emergence of territory and individualism, and
territory was a solution to the problem of how to better ensure one's genes are
being passed on to future generations" (p. 338).
I beg to differ. This explanation of ritual suggests both that dialetics exists
and operates outside of human consciousness (or so it seems to me). However,
ritual consists of actions designed to represent transitions from one stage of
life or on identity to another. Victor Turner, elaborating on the work of Arnold
Van Gennep, has elaborated on how ritual functions in human societies. Ritual
has to do, and is most often invoked, at important developmental or social
moments in human existence---marriage, birth, adulthood, death, etc. Ritual is a
way of helping human beings make these transitions, as well as acknowledging
important social and individual moments, such as thanksgiving rituals that
emerge in agrarian societies to celebrate good crop-bearing seasons. (When I did
fieldwork in Cat Island, Bahamas, I was surprised to learn that they also
celebrated a religious Thanksgiving, but in late October at the end of one
harvest.) Rituals have meaning for human beings, and it is in that meaning that
we can discover how individuality and sociality interact in human life. I am a
firm believer that paradoxes don't exist in nature, only in our ignorance of
nature. Yes, human beings have a tendency to see what Levi-Strauss called binary
oppositions---to divide things that way---but we also know that this is
something that must be overcome through the use of reason if we are to deepen
our understanding of nature, including ourselves.
4. Sexual selection has always been questionable academic enterprise in some of
its many varieties, and reducing human actions solely to its biological
foundations---to claim that passing on one's genes (even when one doesn't know
that genes exist or that males have anything to do with reproduction) ignores
the fact that people have created many rules to control human sexuality. It
seems to me that psychology and culture are the proper levels on which human
reproduction must be considered. Every society has incest taboos, some form of
marriage, and various ways of calculating kinship. Much of this has nothing to
do with territory, individualism (which is different from individuality), or
ritual or "the problem created by the true randomness of sperm and egg mixing
from the spawning of fishes" (p. 338). The conclusions that the author has
reached strike me as an effort to develop a "theory of everything" that is
simply untenable in view of scientific knowledge, and I include the social
sciences here too.
5. "Social movements that oppose privately owned landed property are thus
attempting to overcome nearly half a billion years of evolution. It is no
overstatement to say that opposition to private property is thus atavistic" (p.
338).
Again, the author seems to have formulated a claim with foundations in a
confusion between biological and social evolution, leaving out the all-important
role of society and culture. Communalism is often another term for sociality of
a particular kind. Besides the fact that the evolutionary pattern he traces from
fish to humans is spurious and hardly applicable to social movements, there are
explanations for why people choose to support various social forms---even when
they are wrong. First of all, communalism, holding property in common, functions
as a survival technique. We have seen this phenomenon among street kids in
Brazil and among religious communities that are basically impoverished. Pooling
one's resources guarantees that everyone gets something and has a better chance
of survival than they might have on their own. However, we also know that
communalism breaks down when communities grow in size and become relatively
prosperous---they break down regardless of the ideology of the members. To
maintain communities requires a special effort, lest one lapse out of it
entirely. In fact, there is well recognized pattern that Don Pitzer has called
developmental communalism.
Finally, I think it is difficult to build an entire understanding of dialectics
by seeing it everywhere. What seem to be dialectical relationships, in the end,
may simply be metaphors created by extremely observant artists and other human,
whose brains/minds are designed to discern such patterns, whether they
understand them fully or not. But the important thing in furthering our
understanding is the meaning that people assign to these patterns.
Troy Camplin:
I was purposefully focusing on biological foundations, but that focus in no way
is an argument against social variations. Human universals such as language
necessarily have biological, evolved foundations, but get expressed in all their
variety through the social, through learning. In other words, there is no
conflict at all between my biological and cosmological foundations and the
observations you pull from social science. The entire purpose of social science
is to understand both the underlying structures (structuralism) and varieties
(poststructuralism), with the former being in large part biological in origin.
There's no "mere metaphor," but rather real observations of real
patterns. In this the poets are as important for helping us understand the world
as any scientist, and we lose much understanding by seeing their insights as
"mere metaphors." Indeed, we cannot even communicate without mere metaphors!
1. This is not at all in conflict with anything I wrote.
2. There's no
confusion between biological and social evolution. Biological evolution is
accomplished through Darwinian means (it's more "digital"), while social
evolution is accomplished by Lamarckian means (it's more "analog"), though
selection occurs in both cases. Biological evolution laid the foundations for
both individualism and property, which gets expressed in a variety of ways in a
variety of animals, and which gets expressed in a variety of ways in the human
animal. Laying foundations in no way is the same as claiming you have a finished
house--though you do have to lay the foundations first of all. That's what this
essay was about. The essay could only be so long!
3. Rituals create a
safe play space into which something new can emerge, and primitive forms of
ritual exist in many species of animals (look at all the dances different kinds
of birds do). Rituals are most complexly developed in humans, but are not
exclusive to humans. Coincidentally, I had the privilege of having one if Victor
Turner's sons, Frederick Turner, on my dissertation committee.
.
4. Incest taboos, kinship, and marriage (!) are all intimately connected to
ritual. And they all have everything to do with sexual selection--as do many of
our rituals. Music, dance, poetry, etc. all have their origins in showing off to
get men or women to select mates. You don't have to "know" sex results in
offspring to engage in mating rituals, as the existence of mating rituals in so
many other animals, from gobies to peafowl, shows. Incest taboos have their
roots in the Westermarck effect, which itself has biological origins. Culture
only strengthens it, and includes more and more in its growing circle (to
include cousins, for example). I don't see how any of the social sciences, but
especially anthropology, at all refutes anything I wrote. Again, what I wrote
are foundational to those findings.
5. The examples of communalism don't
disprove my thesis at all. Humans started off as tribal, and we shouldn't be
surprised to find people defaulting to that in crises. Tribalism implies (small)
group ownership--but note that it's always a small group, and that they are
excluding others from the group in order to have the communal ownership. There
also tend to be strong hierarchies of control to make sure there isn't waste.
The key, as you suggest, is size (and complexity). The larger and more complex a
society, the more likely ownership is to fragment. This ensures we get along
better. But, again, I noted that my thesis allows for a huge number of different
kinds of ownership. It just doesn't allow for non-ownership/large-scale-communal
ownership as proposed in Marxism.
Susan Love Brown:
Troy Camplin, tribalism and communalism are not the same thing. In fact, a tribe
is a particular kind of social organization, so I flinch every time I hear the
term "tribalism," which seems to be a contemporary political term to describe
some kind of herd mentality. It's a metaphor. Anyway, I think that in order to
understand each other's point of view, we would have to first agree on some
common terminology. Incidentally, I make a distinction between social evolution
and cultural evolution. What you describe as "Lamarckian" is probably cultural
evolution, although, again, using that term is metaphorical. Culture consists of
ideas that are passed on through learning and modified by experience, not by
selection, which would also be a metaphor in this usage.
Troy Camplin:
Susan Love Brown, all language is metaphorical. And there is group selection.
Some groups survive as groups and some don't. I'll grant there's a difference
between tribalism and communalism, insofar as the latter accepts the existence
of other communal groups and aren't necessarily in competition with each other.
They're at a more complex level in that sense.